Social Anarchism or Lifestyle Anarchism:
An Unbridgeable Chasm
by Murray Bookchin
For some two centuries, anarchism -- a very ecumenical
body of anti-authoritarian ideas -- developed in the tension between two
basically contradictory tendencies: a personalistic commitment to individual
autonomy and a collectivist commitment to social freedom. These tendencies have
by no means been reconciled in the history of libertarian thought. Indeed, for
much of the last century, they simply coexisted within anarchism as a minimalist
credo of opposition to the State rather than as a maximalist credo that
articulated the kind of new society that had to be created in its place.
Which is not to say that various schools of anarchism did not advocate very
specific forms of social organization, albeit often markedly at variance with one
another. Essentially, however, anarchism as a whole advanced what Isaiah Berlin
has called 'negative freedom,' that is to say, a formal 'freedom from,' rather
than a substantive 'freedom to.' Indeed, anarchism often celebrated its
commitment to negative freedom as evidence of its own pluralism, ideological
tolerance, or creativity -- or even, as more than one recent postmodernist
celebrant has argued, its incoherence. Anarchism's failure to resolve this
tension, to articulate the relationship of the individual to the collective, and
to enunciate the historical circumstances that would make possible a stateless
anarchic society produced problems in anarchist thought that remain unresolved to
this day. Pierre Joseph Proudhon, more than many anarchists of his day, attempted
to formulate a fairly concrete image of a libertarian society. Based on
contracts, essentially between small producers, cooperatives, and communes,
Proudhon's vision was redolent of the provincial craft world into which he was
born. But his attempt to meld a patroniste, often patriarchal notion of liberty
with contractual social arrangements was lacking in depth. The craftsman,
cooperative, and commune, relating to one another on bourgeois contractual terms
of equity or justice rather than on the communist terms of ability and needs,
reflected the artisan's bias for personal autonomy, leaving any moral commitment
to a collective undefined beyond the good intentions of its members. Indeed,
Proudhon's famous declaration that 'whoever puts his hand on me to govern me is
an usurper and a tyrant; I declare him my enemy' strongly tilts toward a
personalistic, negative freedom that overshadows his opposition to oppressive
social institutions and the vision of an anarchist society that he projected. His
statement easily blends into William Godwin's distinctly individualistic
declaration: 'There is but one power to which I can yield a heartfelt obedience,
the decision of my own understanding, the dictates of my own conscience.'
Godwin's appeal to the 'authority' of his own understanding and conscience, like
Proudhon's condemnation of the 'hand' that threatens to restrict his liberty,
gave anarchism an immensely individualistic thrust. Compelling as such
declarations may be -- and in the United States they have won considerable
admiration from the so-called libertarian (more accurately, proprietarian) right,
with its avowals of 'free' enterprise -- they reveal an anarchism very much at
odds with itself. By contrast, Michael Bakunin and Peter Kropotkin held
essentially collectivist views -- in Kropotkin's case, explicitly communist ones.
Bakunin emphatically prioritized the social over the individual. Society, he
writes, 'antedates and at the same time survives every human individual,
being in this respect like Nature itself. It is eternal like Nature, or rather,
having been born upon our earth, it will last as long as the earth. A radical
revolt against society would therefore be just as impossible for man as a revolt
against Nature, human society being nothing else but the last great manifestation
or creation of Nature upon this earth. And an individual who would want to rebel
against society . . . would place himself beyond the pale of real
existence.'[1] Bakunin often expressed his opposition to the individualistic
trend in liberalism and anarchism with considerable polemical emphasis. Although
society is 'indebted to individuals,' he wrote in a relatively mild statement,
the formation of the individual is social: 'even the most wretched individual
of our present society could not exist and develop without the cumulative social
efforts of countless generations. Thus the individual, his freedom and reason,
are the products of society, and not vice versa: society is not the product of
individuals comprising it; and the higher, the more fully the individual is
developed, the greater his freedom -- and the more he is the product of society,
the more does he receive from society and the greater his debt to it.'[2]
Kropotkin, for his part, retained this collectivistic emphasis with remarkable
consistency. In what was probably his most widely read work, his Encyclopaedia
Britannica essay on 'Anarchism,' Kropotkin distinctly located the economic
conceptions of anarchism on the 'left-wing' of 'all socialisms,' calling for the
radical abolition of private property and the State in 'the spirit of local and
personal initiative, and of free federation from the simple to the compound, in
lieu of the present hierarchy from the center to the periphery.' Kropotkin's
works on ethics, in fact, include a sustained critique of liberalistic attempts
to counterpose the individual to society, indeed to subordinate society to the
individual or ego. He placed himself squarely in the socialist tradition. His
anarchocommunism, predicated on advances in technology and increased
productivity, became a prevailing libertarian ideology in the 1890s, steadily
elbowing out collectivist notions of distribution based on equity. Anarchists,
'in common with most socialists,' Kropotkin emphasized, recognized the need for
'periods of accelerated evolution which are called revolutions,' ultimately
yielding a society based on federations of 'every township or commune of the
local groups of producers and consumers.'[3] With the emergence of
anarchosyndicalism and anarcho-communism in the late nineteenth and early
twentieth century, the need to resolve the tension between the individualist and
the collectivist tendencies essentially became moot. Anarcho-individualism was
largely marginalized by mass socialistic workers' movements, of which most
anarchists considered themselves the left wing. In an era of stormy social
upheaval, marked by the rise of a mass working-class movement that culminated in
the 1930s and the Spanish Revolution, anarchosyndicalists and anarchocommunists,
no less than Marxists, considered anarcho-individualism to be petty-bourgeois
exotica. They often attacked it quite directly as a middle-class indulgence,
rooted far more in liberalism than in anarchism. The period hardly allowed
individualists, in the name of their 'uniqueness,' to ignore the need for
energetic revolutionary forms of organization with coherent and compelling
programs. Far from indulging in Max Stirner's metaphysics of the ego and its
'uniqueness,' anarchist activists required a basic theoretical, discursive, and
programmatically oriented literature, a need that was filled by, among others,
Kropotkin's The Conquest of Bread (London, 1913), Diego Abad de Santill'n's El
organismo econ'mico de la revoluci'n (Barcelona, 1936), and G. P. Maximoff's The
Political Philosophy of Bakunin (English publication in 1953, three years after
Maximoff's death; the date of original compilation, not provided in the English
translation, may have been years, even decades earlier). No Stirnerite 'Union of
Egoists,' to my knowledge, ever rose to prominence -- even assuming such a union
could be established and survive the 'uniqueness' of its egocentric
participants. Individualist Anarchism and Reaction
To be sure,
ideological individualism did not fade away altogether during this period of
sweeping social unrest. A sizable reservoir of individualist anarchists,
especially in the Anglo-American world, were nourished by the ideas of John Locke
and John Stuart Mill, as well as Stirner himself. Home-grown individualists with
varying degrees of commitment to libertarian views littered the anarchist
horizon. In practice, anarcho-individualism attracted precisely individuals, from
Benjamin Tucker in the United States, an adherent of a quaint version of free
competition, to Federica Montseny in Spain, who often honored her Stirnerite
beliefs in the breach. Despite their avowals of an anarchocommunist ideology,
Nietzscheans like Emma Goldman remained cheek to jowl in spirit with
individualists. Hardly any anarcho-individualists exercised an influence on
the emerging working class. They expressed their opposition in uniquely personal
forms, especially in fiery tracts, outrageous behavior, and aberrant lifestyles
in the cultural ghettos of fin de siècle New York, Paris, and London. As a
credo, individualist anarchism remained largely a bohemian lifestyle, most
conspicuous in its demands for sexual freedom ('free love') and enamored of
innovations in art, behavior, and clothing. It was in times of severe social
repression and deadening social quiescence that individualist anarchists came to
the foreground of libertarian activity -- and then primarily as terrorists. In
France, Spain, and the United States, individualistic anarchists committed acts
of terrorism that gave anarchism its reputation as a violently sinister
conspiracy. Those who became terrorists were less often libertarian socialists or
communists than desperate men and women who used weapons and explosives to
protest the injustices and philistinism of their time, putatively in the name of
'propaganda of the deed.' Most often, however, individualist anarchism expressed
itself in culturally defiant behavior. It came to prominence in anarchism
precisely to the degree that anarchists lost their connection with a viable
public sphere. Today's reactionary social context greatly explains the
emergence of a phenomenon in Euro-American anarchism that cannot be ignored: the
spread of individualist anarchism. In a time when even respectable forms of
socialism are in pell-mell retreat from principles that might in any way be
construed as radical, issues of lifestyle are once again supplanting social
action and revolutionary politics in anarchism. In the traditionally
individualist-liberal United States and Britain, the 1990s are awash in
self-styled anarchists who -- their flamboyant radical rhetoric aside -- are
cultivating a latter-day anarcho-individualism that I will call lifestyle
anarchism. Its preoccupations with the ego and its uniqueness and its
polymorphous concepts of resistance are steadily eroding the socialistic
character of the libertarian tradition. No less than Marxism and other
socialisms, anarchism can be profoundly influenced by the bourgeois environment
it professes to oppose, with the result that the growing 'inwardness' and
narcissism of the yuppie generation have left their mark upon many avowed
radicals. Ad hoc adventurism, personal bravura, an aversion to theory oddly akin
to the antirational biases of postmodernism, celebrations of theoretical
incoherence (pluralism), a basically apolitical and anti-organizational
commitment to imagination, desire, and ecstasy, and an intensely self-oriented
enchantment of everyday life, reflect the toll that social reaction has taken on
Euro-American anarchism over the past two decades. During the 1970s, writes
Katinka Matson, the compiler of a compendium of techniques for personal
psychological development, there occurred 'a remarkable change in the way we
perceive ourselves in the world. The 1960s,' she continues, 'saw a preoccupation
with political activism, Vietnam, ecology, be-ins, communes, drugs, etc. Today we
are turning inward: we are looking for personal definition, personal improvement,
personal achievement, and personal enlightenment.'[4] Matson's noxious little
bestiary, compiled for Psychology Today magazine, covers every technique from
acupuncture to the I Ching, from est to zone therapy. In retrospect, she might
well have included lifestyle anarchism in her compendium of inward-looking
soporifics, most of which foster ideas of individual autonomy rather than social
freedom. Psychotherapy in all its mutations cultivates an inwardly directed
'self' that seeks autonomy in a quiescent psychological condition of emotional
self-sufficiency -- not the socially involved self denoted by freedom. In
lifestyle anarchism as in psychotherapy, the ego is counterposed to the
collective; the self, to society; the personal, to the communal. The ego --
more precisely, its incarnation in various lifestyles -- has become an id'e fixe
for many post-1960s anarchists, who are losing contact with the need for an
organized, collectivistic, programmatic opposition to the existing social order.
Invertebrate 'protests,' directionless escapades, self-assertions, and a very
personal 'recolonization' of everyday life parallel the psychotherapeutic, New
Age, self-oriented lifestyles of bored baby boomers and members of Generation X.
Today, what passes for anarchism in America and increasingly in Europe is little
more than an introspective personalism that denigrates responsible social
commitment; an encounter group variously renamed a 'collective' or an 'affinity
group'; a state of mind that arrogantly derides structure, organization, and
public involvement; and a playground for juvenile antics. Consciously or not,
many lifestyle anarchists articulate Michel Foucault's approach of 'personal
insurrection' rather than social revolution, premised as it is on an ambiguous
and cosmic critique of power as such rather than on a demand for the
institutionalized empowerment of the oppressed in popular assemblies, councils,
and/or confederations. To the extent that this trend rules out the real
possibility of social revolution -- either as an 'impossibility' or as an
'imaginary' -- it vitiates socialistic or communistic anarchism in a fundamental
sense. Indeed, Foucault fosters a perspective that 'resistance is never in a
position of exteriority in relation to power. . . . Hence there is no single
[read: universal] locus of great Refusal, no soul of revolt, source of all
rebellions, or pure law of the revolutionary.' Caught as we all are in the
ubiquitous embrace of a power so cosmic that, Foucault's overstatements and
equivocations aside, resistance becomes entirely polymorphous, we drift futilely
between the 'solitary' and the 'rampant.'[5] His meandering ideas come down to
the notion that resistance must necessarily be a guerrilla war that is always
present -- and that is inevitably defeated. Lifestyle, like individualist,
anarchism bears a disdain for theory, with mystical, and primitivistic filiations
that are generally too vague, intuitional, and even antirational to analyze
directly. They are more properly symptoms than causes of the general drift toward
a sanctification of the self as a refuge from the existing social malaise.
Nonetheless, largely personalistic anarchisms still have certain muddy
theoretical premises that lend themselves to critical examination. Their
ideological pedigree is basically liberal, grounded in the myth of the fully
autonomous individual whose claims to self-sovereignty are validated by axiomatic
'natural rights,' 'intrinsic worth,' or, on a more sophisticated level, an
intuited Kantian transcendental ego that is generative of all knowable reality.
These traditional views surface in Max Stirner's 'I' or ego, which shares with
existentialism a tendency to absorb all of reality into itself, as if the
universe turned on the choices of the self-oriented individual. More recent
works on lifestyle anarchism generally sidestep Stirner's sovereign,
all-encompassing 'I,' albeit retaining its egocentric emphasis, and tend toward
existentialism, recycled Situationism, Buddhism, Taoism, antirationalism, and
primitivism -- or, quite ecumenically, all of them in various permutations. Their
commonalities, as we shall see, are redolent of a prelapsarian return to an
original, often diffuse, and even petulantly infantile ego that ostensibly
precedes history, civilization, and a sophisticated technology -- possibly
language itself -- and they have nourished more than one reactionary political
ideology over the past century. Autonomy or Freedom?
Without falling
into the trap of social constructionism that sees every category as a product of
a given social order, we are obliged to ask for a definition of the 'free
individual.' How does individuality come into being, and under what circumstances
is it free? When lifestyle anarchists call for autonomy rather than freedom,
they thereby forfeit the rich social connotations of freedom. Indeed, today's
steady anarchist drumbeat for autonomy rather than social freedom cannot be
dismissed as accidental, particularly in Anglo-American varieties of libertarian
thought, where the notion of autonomy more closely corresponds to personal
liberty. Its roots lie in the Roman imperial tradition of libertas, wherein the
untrammeled ego is 'free' to own his personal property -- and to gratify his
personal lusts. Today, the individual endowed with 'sovereign rights' is seen by
many lifestyle anarchists as antithetical not only to the State but to society as
such. Strictly defined, the Greek word autonomia means 'independence,'
connoting a self-managing ego, independent of any clientage or reliance on others
for its maintenance. To my knowledge, it was not widely used by the Greek
philosophers; indeed, it is not even mentioned in F. E. Peters's historical
lexicon of Greek Philosophical Terms. Autonomy, like liberty, refers to the man
(or woman) who Plato would have ironically called the 'master of himself,' a
condition 'when the better principle of the human soul controls the worse.' Even
for Plato, the attempt to achieve autonomy through mastery of oneself constituted
a paradox, 'for the master is also the servant and the servant the master, and in
all these modes of speaking the same person is predicated' (Republic, book 4,
431). Characteristically, Paul Goodman, an essentially individualistic anarchist,
maintained that 'for me, the chief principle of anarchism is not freedom but
autonomy, the ability to initiate a task and do it one's own way' -- a view
worthy of an aesthete but not of a social revolutionary.[6] While autonomy is
associated with the presumably self-sovereign individual, freedom dialectically
interweaves the individual with the collective. The word freedom has its analogue
in the Greek eleutheria and derives from the German Freiheit, a term that still
retains a gemeinsch'ftliche or communal ancestry in Teutonic tribal life and law.
When applied to the individual, freedom thus preserves a social or collective
interpretation of that individual's origins and development as a self. In
'freedom,' individual selfhood does not stand opposed to or apart from the
collective but is significantly formed -- and in a rational society, would be
realized -- by his or her own social existence. Freedom thus does not subsume the
individual's liberty but denotes its actualization. The confusion between
autonomy and freedom is all too evident in L. Susan Brown's The Politics of
Individualism (POI), a recent attempt to articulate and elaborate a basically
individualist anarchism, yet retain some filiations with anarcho-communism. [7]
If lifestyle anarchism needs an academic pedigree, it will find it in her attempt
to meld Bakunin and Kropotkin with John Stuart Mill. Alas, herein lies a problem
that is more than academic. Brown's work exhibits the extent to which concepts of
personal autonomy stand at odds with concepts of social freedom. In essence, like
Goodman she interprets anarchism as a philosophy not of social freedom but of
personal autonomy. She then offers a notion of 'existential individualism' that
she contrasts sharply both with 'instrumental individualism' (or C. B.
Macpherson's 'possessive [bourgeois] individualism') and with 'collectivism' --
leavened with extensive quotations from Emma Goldman, who was by no means the
ablest thinker in the libertarian pantheon. Brown's 'existential
individualism' shares liberalism's 'commitment to individual autonomy and
self-determination,' she writes (POI, p. 2). 'While much of anarchist theory has
been viewed as communist by anarchists and non-anarchists alike,' she observes,
'what distinguishes anarchism from other communist philosophies is anarchism's
uncompromising and relentless celebration of individual self-determination and
autonomy. To be an anarchist -- whether communist, individualist, mutualist,
syndicalist, or feminist -- is to affirm a commitment to the primacy of
individual freedom' (POI, p. 2) -- and here she uses the word freedom in the
sense of autonomy. Although anarchism's 'critique of private property and
advocacy of free communal economic relations' (POI, p. 2) move Brown's anarchism
beyond liberalism, it nonetheless upholds individual rights over -- and against
-- those of the collective. 'What distinguishes [existential individualism]
from the collectivist point of view,' Brown goes on, 'is that individualists' --
anarchists no less than liberals -- 'believe in the existence of an internally
motivated and authentic free will, while most collectivists understand the human
individual as shaped externally by others -- the individual for them is
'constructed' by the collective' (POI, p. 12, emphasis added). Essentially, Brown
dismisses collectivism -- not just state socialism, but collectivism as such --
with the liberal canard that a collectivist society entails the subordination of
the individual to the group. Her extraordinary suggestion that 'most
collectivists' have regarded individual people as 'simply human flotsam and
jetsam swept along in the current of history' (POI, p.12) is a case in point.
Stalin certainly held this view, and so did many Bolsheviks, with their
hypostasization of social forces over individual desires and intentions. But
collectivists as such? Are we to ignore the generous traditions of collectivism
that sought a rational, democratic, and harmonious society -- the visions of
William Morris, say, or Gustav Landauer? What about Robert Owen, the Fourierists,
democratic and libertarian socialists, Social Democrats of an earlier era, even
Karl Marx and Peter Kropotkin? I am not sure that 'most collectivists,' even
those who are anarchists, would accept the crude determinism that Brown
attributes to Marx's social interpretations. By creating straw 'collectivists'
who are hard-line mechanists, Brown rhetorically counterposes a mysteriously and
autogenetically constituted individual, on the one hand, with an omnipresent,
presumably oppressive, even totalitarian collective, on the other. Brown, in
effect, overstates the contrast between 'existential individualism' and the
beliefs of 'most collectivists' -- to the point where her arguments seem
misguided at best or disingenuous at worst. It is elementary that,
Jean-Jacques Rousseau's ringing opening to the Social Contract notwithstanding,
people are definitely not 'born free,' let alone autonomous. Indeed, quite to the
contrary, they are born very unfree, highly dependent, and conspicuously
heteronomous. What freedom, independence, and autonomy people have in a given
historical period is the product of long social traditions and, yes, a collective
development -- which is not to deny that individuals play an important role in
that development, indeed are ultimately obliged to do so if they wish to be
free. Brown's argument leads to a surprisingly simplistic conclusion. 'It is
not the group that gives shape to the individual,' we are told, 'but rather
individuals who give form and content to the group. A group is a collection of
individuals, no more and no less; it has no life or consciousness of its own'
(POI, p. 12, emphasis added). Not only does this incredible formulation closely
resemble Margaret Thatcher's notorious statement that there is no such thing as a
society but only individuals; it attests to a positivistic, indeed naive social
myopia in which the universal is wholly separated from the concrete. Aristotle,
one would have thought, resolved this problem when he chided Plato for creating a
realm of ineffable 'forms' that existed apart from their tangible and imperfect
'copies.' It remains true that individuals never form mere 'collections' --
except perhaps in cyberspace; quite to the contrary, even when they seem atomized
and hermetic, they are immensely defined by the relationships they establish or
are obliged to establish with each other, by virtue of their very real existence
as social beings. The idea that a collective -- and by extrapolation, society --
is merely a 'collection of individuals, no more and no less' represents an
'insight' into the nature of human consociation that is hardly liberal but, today
particularly, potentially reactionary. By insistently identifying
collectivism with an implacable social determinism, Brown herself creates an
abstract 'individual,' one that is not even existential in the strictly
conventional sense of the word. Minimally, human existence presupposes the social
and material conditions necessary for the maintenance of life, sanity,
intelligence, and discourse; and the affective qualities Brown regards as
essential for her voluntaristic form of communism: care, concern, and sharing.
Lacking the rich articulation of social relationships in which people are
embedded from birth through maturity to old age, a 'collection of individuals'
such as Brown posits would be, to put it bluntly, not a society at all. It would
be literally a 'collection' in Thatcher's sense of free-booting, self-seeking,
egoistic monads. Presumably complete unto themselves, they are, by dialectical
inversion, immensely de-individuated for want of any aim beyond the satisfaction
of their own needs and pleasures -- which are often socially engineered today in
any case. Acknowledging that individuals are self-motivated and possess free
will does not require us to reject collectivism, given that they are also capable
of developing an awareness of the social conditions under which these eminently
human potentialities are exercised. The attainment of freedom rests partly on
biological facts, as anyone who has raised a child knows; partly, on social
facts, as anyone who lives in a community knows; and contrary to social
constructionists, partly on the interaction of environment and inborn personal
proclivities, as any thinking person knows. Individuality did not spring into
being ab novo. Like the idea of freedom, it has a long social and psychological
history. Left to his or her own self, the individual loses the indispensable
social moorings that make for what an anarchist might be expected to prize in
individuality: reflective powers, which derive in great part from discourse; the
emotional equipment that nourishes rage against unfreedom; the sociality that
motivates the desire for radical change; and the sense of responsibility that
engenders social action. Indeed, Brown's thesis has disturbing implications
for social action. If individual 'autonomy' overrides any commitment to a
'collectivity,' there is no basis whatever for social institutionalization,
decision-making, or even administrative coordination. Each individual,
self-contained in his or her 'autonomy,' is free to do whatever he or she wants
-- presumably, following the old liberal formula, if it does not impede the
'autonomy' of others. Even democratic decision-making is jettisoned as
authoritarian. 'Democratic rule is still rule,' Brown warns. 'While it allows for
more individual participation in government than monarchy or totalitarian
dictatorship, it still inherently involves the repression of the wills of some
people. This is obviously at odds with the existential individual, who must
maintain the integrity of will in order to be existentially free' (POI, p. 53).
Indeed, so transcendentally sacrosanct is the autonomous individual will, in
Brown's eyes, that she approvingly quotes Peter Marshall's claim that, according
to anarchist principles, 'the majority has no more right to dictate to the
minority, even a minority of one, than the minority to the majority' (POI, p.
140, emphasis added). Denigrating rational, discursive, and direct-democratic
procedures for collective decision-making as 'dictating' and 'ruling' awards a
minority of one sovereign ego the right to abort the decision of a majority. But
the fact remains that a free society will either be democratic, or it will not be
achieved at all. In the very existential situation, if you please, of an
anarchist society -- a direct libertarian democracy -- decisions would most
certainly be made following open discussion. Thereafter the outvoted minority --
even a minority of one -- would have every opportunity to present countervailing
arguments to try to change that decision. Decision-making by consensus, on the
other hand, precludes ongoing dissensus -- the all-important process of continual
dialogue, disagreement, challenge, and counter'challenge, without which social as
well as individual creativity would be impossible. If anything, functioning
on the basis of consensus assures that important decision-making will be either
manipulated by a minority or collapse completely. And the decisions that are made
will embody the lowest common denominator of views and constitute the least
creative level of agreement. I speak, here, from painful, years-long experience
with the use of consensus in the Clamshell Alliance of the 1970s. Just at the
moment when this quasi-anarchic antinuclear-power movement was at the peak of its
struggle, with thousands of activists, it was destroyed through the manipulation
of the consensus process by a minority. The 'tyranny of structurelessness' that
consensus decision-making produced permitted a well-organized few to control the
unwieldy, deinstitutionalized, and largely disorganized many within the
movement. Nor, amidst the hue and cry for consensus, was it possible for
dissensus to exist and creatively stimulate discussion, fostering a creative
development of ideas that could yield new and ever-expanding perspectives. In any
community, dissensus -- and dissident individuals -- prevent the community from
stagnating. Pejorative words like dictate and rule properly refer to the
silencing of dissenters, not to the exercise of democracy; ironically, it is the
consensual 'general will' that could well, in Rousseau's memorable phrase from
the Social Contract, 'force men to be free.' Far from being existential in
any earthy sense of the word, Brown's 'existential individualism' deals with the
individual ahistorically. She rarefies the individual as a transcendental
category, much as, in the 1970s, Robert K. Wolff paraded Kantian concepts of the
individual in his dubious Defense of Anarchism. The social factors that interact
with the individual to make him or her a truly willful and creative being are
subsumed under transcendental moral abstractions that, given a purely
intellectual life of their own, 'exist' outside of history and praxis.
Alternating between moral transcendentalism and simplistic positivism in her
approach to the individual's relationship with the collective, Brown's exposition
fits together as clumsily as creationism with evolution. The rich dialectic and
the ample history that shows how the individual was largely formed by and
interacted with a social development is nearly absent from her work. Atomistic
and narrowly analytic in many of her views, yet abstractly moral and even
transcendental in her interpretations, Brown provides an excellent setting for a
notion of autonomy that is antipodal to social freedom. With the 'existential
individual' on one side, and a society that consists of a 'collection of
individuals' and nothing more on the other, the chasm between autonomy and
freedom becomes unbridgeable. Anarchism as Chaos
Whatever Brown's
own preferences may be, her book both reflects and provides the premises for the
shift among Euro-American anarchists away from social anarchism and toward
individualist or lifestyle anarchism. Indeed, lifestyle anarchism today is
finding its principal expression in spray-can graffiti, post-modernist nihilism,
antirationalism, neoprimitivism, anti-technologism, neo-Situationist 'cultural
terrorism,' mysticism, and a 'practice' of staging Foucauldian 'personal
insurrections.' These trendy posturings, nearly all of which follow current
yuppie fashions, are individualistic in the important sense that they are
antithetical to the development of serious organizations, a radical politics, a
committed social movement, theoretical coherence, and programmatic relevance.
More oriented toward achieving one's own 'self-realization' than achieving basic
social change, this trend among lifestyle anarchists is particularly noxious in
that its 'turning inward,' as Katinka Matson called it, claims to be a politics
-- albeit one that resembles R. D. Laing's 'politics of experience.' The black
flag, which revolutionary social anarchists raised in insurrectionary struggles
in Ukraine and Spain, now becomes a fashionable sarong for the delectation of
chic petty bourgeois. One of the most unsavory examples of lifestyle
anarchism is Hakim Bey's (aka Peter Lamborn Wilson's) T.A.Z.: The Temporary
Autonomous Zone, Ontological Anarchism, Poetic Terrorism, a jewel in the New
Autonomy Series (no accidental word choice here), published by the heavily
postmodernist Semiotext(e)/Autono'media group in Brooklyn.[8] Amid paeans to
'Chaos,' 'Amour Fou,' 'Wild Children,' 'Paganism,' 'Art Sabotage,' 'Pirate
Utopias,' 'Black Magic as Revolutionary Action,' 'Crime,' and 'Sorcery,' not to
speak of commendations of 'Marxism-Stirnerism,' the call for autonomy is taken to
lengths so absurd as to seemingly parody a self-absorbed and self-absorbing
ideology. T.A.Z. presents itself as a state of mind, an ardently antirational
and anticivilizational mood, in which disorganization is conceived as an art form
and graffiti supplants programs. The Bey (his pseudonym is the Turkish word for
'chief' or 'prince') minces no words about his disdain for social revolution:
'Why bother to confront a 'power' which has lost all meaning and become sheer
Simulation? Such confrontations will only result in dangerous and ugly spasms of
violence' (TAZ, p. 128). Power in quotation marks? A mere 'Simulation'? If what
is happening in Bosnia with firepower is a mere 'simulation,' we are living in a
very safe and comfortable world indeed! The reader uneasy about the steadily
multiplying social pathologies of modern life may be comforted by the Bey's
Olympian thought that 'realism demands not only that we give up waiting for 'the
Revolution,' but also that we give up wanting it' (TAZ, p. 101). Does this
passage beckon us to enjoy the serenity of Nirvana? Or a new Baudrillardian
'Simulation'? Or perhaps a new Castoriadian 'imaginary'? Having eliminated
the classical revolutionary aim of transforming society, the Bey patronizingly
mocks those who once risked all for it: 'The democrat, the socialist, the
rational ideology . . . are deaf to the music & lack all sense of rhythm'
(TAZ, p. 66). Really? Have the Bey and his acolytes themselves mastered the
verses and music of the Marseillaise and danced ecstatically to the rhythms of
Gliere's Russian Sailor's Dance? There is a wearisome arrogance in the Bey's
dismissal of the rich culture that was created by revolutionaries over the past
centuries, indeed by ordinary working people in the pre-rock-'n'-roll,
pre-Woodstock era. Verily, let anyone who enters the dreamworld of the Bey
give up all nonsense about social commitment. 'A democratic dream? a socialist
dream? Impossible,' intones the Bey with overbearing certainty. 'In dream we are
never ruled except by love or sorcery' (TAZ, p. 64). Thus are the dreams of a new
world evoked by centuries of idealists in great revolutions magisterially reduced
by the Bey to the wisdom of his febrile dream world. As to an anarchism that
is 'all cobwebby with Ethical Humanism, Free Thought, Muscular Atheism, &
crude Fundamentalist Cartesian Logic' (TAZ, p. 52) -- forget it! Not only does
the Bey, with one fell swoop, dispose of the Enlightenment tradition in which
anarchism, socialism, and the revolutionary movement were once rooted, he mixes
apples like 'Fundamentalist Cartesian Logic' with oranges like 'Free Thought,'
and 'Muscular Humanism' as though they were interchangeable or necessarily
presuppose each other. Although the Bey himself never hesitates to issue
Olympian pronouncements and deliver petulant polemics, he has no patience with
'the squabbling ideologues of anarchism & libertarianism' (TAZ, p. 46).
Proclaiming that 'Anarchy knows no dogmas' (TAZ, p. 52), the Bey nonetheless
immerses his readers in a harsh dogma if there ever was one: 'Anarchism
ultimately implies anarchy -- & anarchy is chaos' (TAZ, p. 64). So saith the
Lord: 'I Am That I Am' -- and Moses quaked before the pronouncement! Indeed,
in a fit of manic narcissism, the Bey ordains that it is the all-possessive self,
the towering 'I,' the Big 'me' that is sovereign: 'each of us [is] the ruler of
our own flesh, our own creations -- and as much of everything else as we can grab
& hold.' For the Bey, anarchists and kings -- and beys -- become
indistinguishable, inasmuch as all are autarchs: Our actions are justified by
fiat & our relations are shaped by treaties with other autarchs. We make the
law for our own domains -- & the chains of law have been broken. At present
perhaps we survive as mere Pretenders -- but even so we may seize a few instants,
a few square feet of reality over which to impose our absolute will, our royaume.
L'etat, c'est moi. . . . If we are bound by any ethics or morality, it must be
one which we ourselves have imagined. (TAZ, p. 67) L'Etat, c'est moi? Along
with beys, I can think of at least two people in this century who did enjoy these
sweeping prerogatives: Joseph Stalin and Adolf Hitler. Most of the rest of us
mortals, rich and poor alike, share, as Anatole France once put it, the
prohibition to sleep under the bridges of the Seine. Indeed, if Friedrich
Engels's 'On Authority,' with its defense of hierarchy, represents a bourgeois
form of socialism, T.A.Z. and its offshoots represent a bourgeois form of
anarchism. 'There is no becoming,' the Bey tells us, 'no revolution, no struggle,
no path; [if] already you're the monarch of your own skin -- your inviolable
freedom awaits to be completed only by the love of other monarchs: a politics of
dream, urgent as the blueness of sky' -- words that could be inscribed on the New
York Stock Exchange as a credo for egotism and social indifference (TAZ, p.
4). Certainly, this view will not repel the boutiques of capitalist 'culture'
any more than long hair, beards, and jeans have repelled the entrepreneurial
world of haute fashion. Unfortunately, far too many people in this world -- no
'simulations' or 'dreams' -- do not own even their own skins, as prisoners in
chain gangs and jails can attest in the most concrete of terms. No one has ever
floated out of the earthly realm of misery on 'a politics of dreams' except the
privileged petty bourgeois, who may find the Bey's manifestoes amenable
particularly in moments of boredom. For the Bey, in fact, even classical
revolutionary insurrections offer little more than a personal high, redolent of
Foucault's 'limit experiences.' 'An uprising is like a 'peak experience,'' he
assures us (TAZ, p. 100). Historically, 'some anarchists . . took part in all
sorts of uprisings and revolutions, even communist & socialist ones,' but
that was 'because they found in the moment of insurrection itself the kind of
freedom they sought. Thus while utopianism has so far always failed, the
individualist or existentialist anarchists have succeeded inasmuch as they have
attained (however briefly) the realization of their will to power in war' (TAZ,
p. 88). The Austrian workers' uprising of February 1934 and the Spanish Civil War
of 1936, I can attest, were more than orgiastic 'moments of insurrection' but
were bitter struggles carried on with desperate earnestness and magnificent 'lan,
all aesthetic epiphanies notwithstanding. Insurrection nonetheless becomes
for the Bey little more than a psychedelic 'trip,' while the Nietzschean Overman,
of whom the Bey approves, is a 'free spirit' who would 'disdain wasting time on
agitation for reform, on protest, on visionary dreams, on all kinds of
'revolutionary martyrdom.'' Presumably dreams are okay as long as they are not
'visionary' (read: socially committed); rather, the Bey would 'drink wine' and
have a 'private epiphany' (TAZ, p. 88), which suggests little more than mental
masturbation, freed to be sure from the constraints of Cartesian logic. It
should not surprise us to learn that the Bey favors the ideas of Max Stirner, who
'commits no metaphysics, yet bestows on the Unique [i.e, the Ego] a certain
absoluteness' (TAZ, p. 68). To be sure, the Bey finds that there is a 'missing
ingredient in Stirner': 'a working concept of nonordinary consciousness' (TAZ, p.
68). Apparently Stirner is too much the rationalist for the Bey. 'The orient, the
occult, the tribal cultures possess techniques which can be 'appropriated' in
true anarchist fashion. . . . We need a practical kind of 'mystical anarchism' .
. . a democratization of shamanism, intoxicated & serene' (TAZ, p. 63). Hence
the Bey summons his disciples to become 'sorcerers' and suggests that they use
the 'Black Malay Djinn Curse.' What, finally, is a 'temporary autonomous
zone'? 'The TAZ is like an uprising which does not engage directly with the
State, a guerrilla operation which liberates an area (of land, of time, of
imagination) and then dissolves itself, to re-form elsewhere/elsewhen, before the
State can crush it' (TAZ, p. 101). In a TAZ we can 'realize many of our true
Desires, even if only for a season, a brief Pirate Utopia, a warped free-zone in
the old Space/Time continuum)' (TAZ, p. 62). 'Potential TAZs' include 'the
sixties-style 'tribal gathering,' the forest conclave of eco-saboteurs, the
idyllic Beltane of the neopagans, anarchist conferences, and gay faery circles,'
not to speak of 'nightclubs, banquets,' and 'old-time libertarian picnics' -- no
less! (TAZ, p. 100). Having been a member of the Libertarian League in the 1960s,
I would love to see the Bey and his disciples surface at an 'old-time libertarian
picnic'! So transient, so evanescent, so ineffable is a TAZ in contrast to
the formidably stable State and bourgeoisie that 'as soon as the TAZ is named . .
. it must vanish, it will vanish . . . only to spring up again somewhere else'
(TAZ, p. 101). A TAZ, in effect, is not a revolt but precisely a simulation, an
insurrection as lived in the imagination of a juvenile brain, a safe retreat into
unreality. Indeed, declaims the Bey: 'We recommend [the TAZ] because it can
provide the quality of enhancement without necessarily [!] leading to violence
& martyrdom' (TAZ, p. 101). More precisely, like an Andy Warhol 'happening,'
a TAZ is a passing event, a momentary orgasm, a fleeting expression of the 'will
to power' that is, in fact, conspicuously powerless in its capacity to leave any
imprint on the individual's personality, subjectivity, and even self-formation,
still less on shaping events and reality. Given the evanescent quality of a
TAZ, the Bey's disciples can enjoy the fleeting privilege of living a 'nomadic
existence,' for 'homelessness can in a sense be a virtue, an adventure' (TAZ, p.
130). Alas, homelessness can be an 'adventure' when one has a comfortable home to
return to, while nomadism is the distinct luxury of those who can afford to live
without earning their livelihood. Most of the 'nomadic' hoboes I recall so
vividly from the GreatDepression era suffered desperate lives of hunger, disease,
and indignity and usually died prematurely -- as they still do, today, in the
streets of urban America. The few gypsy-types who seemed to enjoy the 'life of
the road' were idiosyncratic at best and tragically neurotic at worst. Nor can I
ignore another 'insurrection' that the Bey advances: notably, 'voluntary
illiteracy' (TAZ, p. 129). Although he advances this as a revolt against the
educational system, its more desirable effect might be to render the Bey's
various ex cathedra injunctions inaccessible to his readers. Perhaps no
better description can be given of T.A.Z.'s message than the one that appeared in
Whole Earth Review, whose reviewer emphasizes that the Bey's pamphlet is 'quickly
becom[ing] the countercultural bible of the 1990s . . . While many of Bey's
concepts share an affinity with the doctrines of anarchism,' the Review reassures
its yuppie clientele that he pointedly departs from the usual rhetoric about
overthrowing the government. Instead, he prefers the mercurial nature of
'uprisings,' which he believes provide 'moments of intensity [that can] give
shape and meaning to the entirety of life.' These pockets of freedom, or
temporary autonomous zones, enable the individual to elude the schematic grids of
Big Government and to occasionally live within realms where he or she can briefly
experience total freedom. (emphasis added) [9] There is an untranslatable
Yiddish word for all of this: nebbich! During the 1960s, the affinity group Up
Against the Wall Motherfuckers spread similar confusion, disorganization, and
'cultural terrorism,' only to disappear from the political scene soon thereafter.
Indeed, some of its members entered the commercial, professional, and
middle-class world they had formerly professed to despise. Nor is such behavior
uniquely American. As one French 'veteran' of May-June 1968 cynically put it: 'We
had our fun in '68, and now it's time to grow up.' The same deadening cycle, with
circled A's, was repeated during a highly individualistic youth revolt in Zurich
in 1984, only to end in the creation of Needle Park, a notorious cocaine and
crack hangout established by the city's officials to allow addicted young people
to destroy themselves legally. The bourgeoisie has nothing whatever to fear
from such lifestyle declamations. With its aversion for institutions, mass-based
organizations, its largely subcultural orientation, its moral decadence, its
celebration of transience, and its rejection of programs, this kind of
narcissistic anarchism is socially innocuous, often merely a safety valve for
discontent toward the prevailing social order. With the Bey, lifestyle anarchism
takes flight from all meaningful social activism and a steadfast commitment to
lasting and creative projects by dissolving itself into kicks, postmodernist
nihilism, and a dizzying Nietzschean sense of elitist superiority. The price
that anarchism will pay if it permits this swill to displace the libertarian
ideals of an earlier period could be enormous. The Bey's egocentric anarchism,
with its post-modernist withdrawal into individualistic 'autonomy,' Foucauldian
'limit experiences,' and neo-Situationist 'ecstasy,' threatens to render the very
word anarchism politically and socially harmless -- a mere fad for the
titillation of the petty bourgeois of all ages. Mystical and
Irrationalist Anarchism
The Bey's T.A.Z. hardly stands alone in its appeal
to sorcery, even mysticism. Given their prelapsarian mentality, many lifestyle
anarchists readily take to antirationalism in its most atavistic forms. Consider
'The Appeal of Anarchy,' which occupies the entire back page of a recent issue of
Fifth Estate (Summer 1989). 'Anarchy,' we read, recognizes 'the imminence of
total liberation [nothing less!] and as a sign of your freedom, be naked in your
rites.' Engage in 'dancing, singing, laughing, feasting, playing,' we are
enjoined -- and could anyone short of a mummified prig argue against these
Rabelaisian delights? But unfortunately, there is a hitch. Rabelais's Abbey
of Thélème, which Fifth Estate seems to emulate, was replete with servants,
cooks, grooms, and artisans, without whose hard labor the self-indulgent
aristocrats of his distinctly upper-class utopia would have starved and huddled
naked in the otherwise cold halls of the Abbey. To be sure, the Fifth Estate's
'Appeal of Anarchy' may well have in mind a materially simpler version of the
Abbey of Thélème, and its 'feasting' may refer more to tofu and rice than to
stuffed partridges and tasty truffles. But still -- without major technological
advances to free people from toil, even to get tofu and rice on the table, how
could a society based on this version of anarchy hope to 'abolish all authority,'
'share all things in common,' feast, and run naked, dancing and singing? This
question is particularly relevant for the Fifth Estate group. What is arresting
in the periodical is the primitivistic, prerational, antitechnological, and
anticivilizational cult that lies at the core of its articles. Thus Fifth
Estate's 'Appeal' invites anarchists to 'cast the magic circle, enter the trance
of ecstasy, revel in sorcery which dispels all power' -- precisely the magical
techniques that shamans (who at least one of its writers celebrates) in tribal
society, not to speak of priests in more developed societies, have used for ages
to elevate their status as hierarchs and against which reason long had to battle
to free the human mind from its own self-created mystifications. 'Dispel all
power'? Again, there is a touch of Foucault here that as always denies the need
for establishing distinctly empowered self-managing institutions against the very
real power of capitalist and hierarchical institutions -- indeed, for the
actualization of a society in which desire and ecstasy can find genuine
fulfillment in a truly libertarian communism. Fifth Estate's beguilingly
'ecstatic' paean to 'anarchy,' so bereft of social content -- all its rhetorical
flourishes aside -- could easily appear as a poster on the walls of a chic
boutique, or on the back of a greeting card. Friends who recently visited New
York City advise me, in fact, that a restaurant with linen-covered tables, fairly
expensive menus, and a yuppie clientele on St. Mark's Place in the Lower East
Side -- a battleground of the 1960s -- is named Anarchy. This feedlot for the
city's petty bourgeoisie sports a print of the famous Italian mural The Fourth
Estate, which shows insurrectionary fin de si'cle workers militantly marching
against an undepicted boss or possibly a police station. Lifestyle anarchism, it
would seem, can easily become a choice consumer delicacy. The restaurant, I am
told, also has security guards, presumably to keep out the local canaille who
figure in the mural. Safe, privatistic, hedonistic, and even cozy, lifestyle
anarchism may easily provide the ready verbiage to spice up the pedestrian
bourgeois lifeways of timid Rabelaisians. Like the 'Situationist art' that MIT
displayed for the delectation of the avant-garde petty bourgeoisie several years
ago, it offers little more than a terribly 'wicked' anarchist image -- dare I
say, a simulacrum -- like those that flourish all along the Pacific Rim of
America and points east'ward. The Ecstasy Industry, for its part, is doing only
too well under contemporary capitalism and could easily absorb the techniques of
lifestyle anarchists to enhance a marketably naughty image. The counterculture
that once shocked the petty bourgeoisie with its long hair, beards, dress, sexual
freedom, and art has long since been upstaged by bourgeois entrepreneurs whose
boutiques, caf's, clubs, and even nudist camps are doing a flourishing 'business,
as witness the many steamy advertisements for new 'ecstasies' in the Village
Voice and similar periodicals. Actually, Fifth Estate's blatantly
antirationalistic sentiments have very troubling implications. Its visceral
celebration of imagination, ecstasy, and 'primality' patently impugns not only
rationalistic efficiency but reason as such. The cover of the Fall/Winter 1993
issue bears Francisco Goya's famously misunderstood Capriccio no. 43, 'Il sueno
de la razon produce monstros' ('The sleep of reason produces monsters'). Goya's
sleeping figure is shown slumped over his desk before an Apple computer. Fifth
Estate's English translation of Goya's inscription reads, 'The dream of reason
produces monsters,' implying that monsters are a product of reason itself. In
point of fact, Goya avowedly meant, as his own notes indicate, that the monsters
in the engraving are produced by the sleep, not the dream, of reason. As he wrote
in his own commentary: 'Imagination, deserted by reason, begets impossible
monsters. United with reason, she is the mother of all arts, and the source of
their wonders.'[10] By deprecating reason, this on-again, off-again anarchist
periodical enters into collusion with some of the most dismal aspects of today's
neo-Heideggerian reaction. Against Technology and Civilization
Even
more troubling are the writings of George Bradford (aka David Watson), one of the
major theorists at Fifth Estate, on the horrors of technology -- apparently
technology as such. Technology, it would seem, determines social relations rather
than the opposite, a notion that more closely approximates vulgar Marxism than,
say, social ecology. 'Technology is not an isolated project, or even an
accumulation of technical knowledge,' Bradford tells us in 'Stopping the
Industrial Hydra' (SIH), that is determined by a somehow separate and more
fundamental sphere of 'social relations.' Mass technics have become, in the words
of Langdon Winner, 'structures whose conditions of operation demand the
restructuring of their environments,' and thus of the very social relations that
brought them about. Mass technics -- a product of earlier forms and archaic
hierarchies -- have now outgrown the conditions that engendered them, taking on
an autonomous life. . . . They furnish, or have become, a kind of total
environment and social system, both in their general and individual, subjective
aspects. . . . In such a mechanized pyramid . . . instrumental and social
relations are one and the same.[11] This facile body of notions comfortably
bypasses the capitalist relations that blatantly determine how technology will be
used and focuses on what technology is presumed to be. By relegating social
relations to something less than fundamental -- instead of emphasizing the
all-important productive process where technology is used -- Bradford imparts to
machines and 'mass technics' a mystical autonomy that, like the Stalinist
hypostasization of technology, has served extremely reactionary ends. The idea
that technology has a life of its own is deeply rooted in the conservative German
romanticism of the last century and in the writings of Martin Heidegger and
Friedrich Georg J'nger, which fed into National Socialist ideology, however much
the Nazis honored their antitechnological ideology in the breach. Viewed in
terms of the contemporary ideology of our own times, this ideological baggage is
typified by the claim, so common today, that newly developed automated machinery
variously costs people their jobs or intensifies their exploitation -- both of
which are indubitable facts but are anchored precisely in social relations of
capitalist exploitation, not in technological advances per se. Stated bluntly:
'downsizing' today is not being done by machines but by avaricious bourgeois who
use machines to replace labor or exploit it more intensively. Indeed, the very
machines that the bourgeois employs to reduce 'labor costs' could, in a rational
society, free human beings from mindless toil for more creative and personally
rewarding activities. There is no evidence that Bradford is familiar with
Heidegger or J'nger; rather, he seems to draw his inspiration from Langdon Winner
and Jacques Ellul, the latter of whom Bradford quotes approvingly: 'It is the
technological coherence that now makes up the social coherence. . . . Technology
is in itself not only a means, but a universe of means -- in the original sense
of Universum: both exclusive and total' (quoted in SIH, p. 10). In The
Technological Society, his best-known book, Ellul advanced the dour thesis that
the world and our ways of thinking about it are patterned on tools and machines
(la technique). Lacking any social explanation of how this 'technological
society' came about, Ellul's book concluded by offering no hope, still less any
approach for redeeming humanity from its total absorption by la technique.
Indeed, even a humanism that seeks to harness technology to meet human needs is
reduced, in his view, into a 'pious hope with no chance whatsoever of influencing
technological evolution.' [12] And rightly so, if so deterministic a worldview is
followed to its logical conclusion. Happily, however, Bradford provides us
with a solution: 'to begin immediately to dismantle the machine altogether' (SIH,
p. 10). And he brooks no compromise with civilization but essentially repeats all
the quasi-mystical, anticivilizational, and antitechnological clich's that appear
in certain New Age environmental cults. Modern civilization, he tells us, is 'a
matrix of forces,' including 'commodity relations, mass communications,
urbanization and mass technics, along with . . . interlocking, rival
nuclear-cybernetic states,' all of which converge into a 'global megamachine'
(SIH, p. 20). 'Commodity relations,' he notes in his essay 'Civilization in Bulk'
(CIB), are merely part of this 'matrix of forces,' in which civilization is 'a
machine' that has been a 'labor camp from its origins,' a 'rigid pyramid of
crusting hierarchies,' 'a grid expanding the territory of the inorganic,' and 'a
linear progression from Prometheus' theft of fire to the International Monetary
Fund.' [13] Accordingly, Bradford reproves Monica Sj'o and Barbara Mor's inane
book, The Great Cosmic Mother: Rediscovering the Religion of the Earth -- not for
its atavistic and regressive theism, but because the authors put the word
civilization in quotation marks -- a practice that 'reflects the tendency of this
fascinating [!] book to posit an alternative or reverse perspective on
civilization rather than to challenge its terms altogether' (CIB, footnote 23).
Presumably, it is Prometheus who is to be reproved, not these two Earth Mothers,
whose tract on chthonic deities, for all its compromises with civilization, is
'fascinating.' No reference to the megamachine would be complete, to be sure,
without quoting from Lewis Mumford's lament on its social effects. Indeed, it is
worth noting that such comments have normally misconstrued Mumford's intentions.
Mumford was not an antitechnologist, as Bradford and others would have us
believe; nor was he in any sense of the word a mystic who would have found
Bradford's anticivilizational primitivism to his taste. On this score, I can
speak from direct personal knowledge of Mumford's views, when we conversed at
some length as participants in a conference at the University of Pennsylvania
around 1972. But one need only turn to his writings, such as Technics and
Civilization (TAC), from which Bradford himself quotes, to see that Mumford is at
pains to favorably describe 'mechanical instruments' as 'potentially a vehicle of
rational human purposes.' [14] Repeatedly reminding his reader that machines come
from human beings, Mumford emphasizes that the machine is 'the projection of one
particular side of the human personality' (TAC, p. 317). Indeed, one of its most
important functions has been to dispel the impact of superstition on the human
mind. Thus: In the past, the irrational and demonic aspects of life had
invaded spheres where they did not belong. It was a step in advance to discover
that bacteria, not brownies, were responsible for curdling milk, and that an
air-cooled motor was more effective than a witch's broomstick for rapid long
distance transportation. . . . Science and technics stiffened our morale: by
their very austerities and abnegations they . . . cast contempt on childish
fears, childish guesses, equally childish assertions. (TAC, p. 324) This
major theme in Mumford's writings has been blatantly neglected by the
primitivists in our midst -- notably, his belief that the machine has made the
'paramount contribution' of fostering 'the technique of cooperative thought and
action.' Nor did Mumford hesitate to praise 'the esthetic excellence of the
machine form . . . above all, perhaps, the more objective personality that has
come into existence through a more sensitive and understanding intercourse with
these new social instruments and through their deliberate cultural assimilation'
(TAC, p. 324). Indeed, 'the technique of creating a neutral world of fact as
distinguished from the raw data of immediate experience was the great general
contribution of modern analytic science' (TAC, p. 361). Far from sharing
Bradford's explicit primitivism, Mumford sharply criticized those who reject the
machine absolutely, and he regarded the 'return to the absolute primitive' as a
'neurotic adaptation' to the megamachine itself (TAC, p. 302), indeed a
catastrophe. 'More disastrous than any mere physical destruction of machines by
the barbarian is his threat to turn off or divert the human motive power,' he
observed in the sharpest of terms, 'discouraging the cooperative processes of
thought and the disinterested research which are responsible for our major
technical achievements' (TAC, p. 302). And he enjoined: 'We must abandon our
futile and lamentable dodges for resisting the machine by stultifying relapses
into savagery' (TAC, p. 319). Nor do his later works reveal any evidence that
he relented in this view. Ironically, he contemptuously designated the Living
Theater's performances and visions of the 'Outlaw Territory' of motorcycle gangs
as 'Barbarism,' and he deprecated Wood'stock as the 'Mass Mobilization of Youth,'
from which the 'present mass-minded, over-regimented, depersonalized culture has
nothing to fear.' Mumford, for his own part, favored neither the megamachine
nor primitivism (the 'organic') but rather the sophistication of technology along
democratic and humanly scaled lines. 'Our capacity to go beyond the machine [to a
new synthesis] rests upon our power to assimilate the machine,' he observed in
Technics and Civilization. 'Until we have absorbed the lessons of objectivity,
impersonality, neutrality, the lessons of the mechanical realm, we cannot go
further in our development toward the more richly organic, the more profoundly
human' (TAC, p. 363, emphasis added). Denouncing technology and civilization
as inherently oppressive of humanity in fact serves to veil the specific social
relations that privilege exploiters over the exploited and hierarchs over their
subordinates. More than any oppressive society in the past, capitalism conceals
its exploitation of humanity under a disguise of 'fetishes,' to use Marx's
terminology in Capital, above all, the 'fetishism of commodities,' which has been
variously -- and superficially -- embroidered by the Situationists into
'spectacles' and by Baudrillard into 'simulacra.' Just as the bourgeoisie's
acquisition of surplus value is hidden by a contractual exchange of wages for
labor power that is only ostensibly equal, so the fetishization of the commodity
and its movements conceals the sovereignty of capitalism's economic and social
relations. There is an important, indeed crucial, point to be made, here.
Such concealment shields from public purview the causal role of capitalist
competition in producing the crises of our times. To these mystifications,
antitechnologists and anticivilizationists add the myth of technology and
civilization as inherently oppressive, and they thus obscure the social
relationships unique to capitalism -- notably the use of things (commodities,
exchange values, objects -- employ what terms you choose) to mediate social
relations and produce the techno-urban landscape of our time. Just as the
substitution of the phrase 'industrial society' for capitalism obscures the
specific and primary role of capital and commodity relationships in forming
modern society, so the substitution of a techno-urban culture for social
relations, in which Bradford overtly engages, conceals the primary role of the
market and competition in forming modern culture. Lifestyle anarchism,
largely because it is concerned with a 'style' rather than a society, glosses
over capitalist accumulation, with its roots in the competitive marketplace, as
the source of ecological devastation, and gazes as if transfixed at the alleged
break of humanity's 'sacred' or 'ecstatic' unity with 'Nature' and at the
'disenchantment of the world' by science, materialism, and 'logocentricity.'
Thus, instead of disclosing the sources of present-day social and personal
pathologies, antitechnologism allows us to speciously replace capitalism with
technology, which basically facilitates capital accumulation and the exploitation
of labor, as the underlying cause of growth and of ecological destruction.
Civilization, embodied in the city as a cultural center, is divested of its
rational dimensions, as if the city were an unabated cancer rather than the
potential sphere for universalizing human intercourse, in marked contrast to the
parochial limitations of tribal and village life. The basic social relationships
of capitalist exploitation and domination are overshadowed by metaphysical
generalizations about the ego and la technique, blurring public insight into the
basic causes of social and ecological crises -- commodity relations that spawn
the corporate brokers of power, industry, and wealth. Which is not to deny
that many technologies are inherently domineering and ecologically dangerous, or
to assert that civilization has been an unmitigated blessing. Nuclear reactors,
huge dams, highly centralized industrial complexes, the factory system, and the
arms industry -- like bureaucracy, urban blight, and contemporarymedia -- have
been pernicious almost from their inception. But the eighteenth and nineteenth
centuries did not require the steam engine, mass manufacture, or, for that
matter, giant cities and far-reaching bureaucracies, to deforest huge areas of
North America and virtually obliterate its aboriginal peoples, or erode the soil
of entire regions. To the contrary, even before railroads reached out to all
parts of the land, much of this devastation had already been wrought using simple
axes, black-powder muskets, horse-driven wagons, and moldboard plows. It was
these simple technologies that bourgeois enterprise -- the barbarous dimensions
of civilization of the last century -- used to carve much of the Ohio River
valley into speculative real estate. In the South, plantation owners needed slave
'hands' in great part because the machinery to plant and pick cotton did not
exist; indeed, American tenant farming has disappeared over the past two
generations largely because new machinery was introduced to replace the labor of
'freed' black sharecroppers. In the nineteenth century peasants from semifeudal
Europe, following river and canal routes, poured into the American wilderness
and, with eminently unecological methods, began to produce the grains that
eventually propelled American capitalism to economic hegemony in the world.
Bluntly put: it was capitalism -- the commodity relationship expanded to its full
historical proportions -- that produced the explosive environmental crisis of
modern times, beginning with early cottage-made commodities that were carried
over the entire world in sailing vessels, powered by wind rather than engines.
Apart from the textile villages and towns of Britain, where mass manufacture made
its historic breakthrough, the machines that meet with the greatest opprobrium
these days were created long after capitalism gained ascendancy in many parts of
Europe and North America. Despite the current swing of the pendulum from a
glorification of European civilization to its wholesale denigration, however, we
would do well to remember the significance of the rise of modern secularism,
scientific knowledge, universalism, reason, and technologies that potentially
offer the hope of a rational and emancipatory dispensation of social affairs,
indeed, for the full realization of desire and ecstasy without the many servants
and artisans who pandered to the appetites of their aristocratic 'betters' in
Rabelais's Abbey of Thélème. Ironically, the anti'civilizational anarchists who
denounce civilization today are among those who enjoy its cultural fruits and
make expansive, highly individualistic professions of liberty, with no sense of
the painstaking developments in European history that made them possible.
Kropotkin, for one, significantly emphasized 'the progress of modern technics,
which wonderfully simplifies the production of all the necessaries of life.' [15]
To those who lack a sense of historical contextuality, arrogant hindsight comes
cheaply. Mystifying the Primitive
The corollary of antitechnologism
and anticivilizationism is primitivism, an edenic glorification of prehistory and
the desire to somehow return to its putative innocence. Lifestyle anarchists like
Bradford draw their inspiration from aboriginal peoples and myths of an edenic
prehistory. Primal peoples, he says, 'refused technology' -- they 'minimized the
relative weight of instrumental or practical techniques and expanded the
importance of . . . ecstatic techniques.' This was because aboriginal peoples,
with their animistic beliefs, were saturated by a 'love' of animal life and
wilderness -- for them, 'animals, plants, and natural objects' were 'persons,
even kin' (CIB, p. 11). Accordingly, Bradford objects to the 'official' view
that designates the lifeways of prehistoric foraging cultures as 'terrible,
brutish and nomadic, a bloody struggle for existence.' Rather, he apotheosizes
'the primal world' as what Marshall Sahlins called 'the original affluent
society,' affluent because its needs are few, all its desires are easily met.
Its tool kit is elegant and light-weight, its outlook linguistically complex and
conceptually profound yet simple and accessible to all. Its culture is expansive
and ecstatic. It is propertyless and communal, egalitarian and cooperative. . . .
It is anarchic. . . . free of work . . . It is a dancing society, a singing
society, a celebrating society, a dreaming society. (CIB, p. 10) Inhabitants
of the 'primal world,' according to Bradford, lived in harmony with the natural
world and enjoyed all the benefits of affluence, including much leisure time.
Primal society, he emphasizes, was 'free of work' since hunting and gathering
required much less effort than people today put in with the eight-hour day. He
does compassionately concede that primal society was 'capable of experiencing
occasional hunger.' This 'hunger,' however, was really symbolic and
self-inflicted, you see, because primal peoples 'sometimes [chose] hunger to
enhance interrelatedness, to play, or to see visions' (CIB, p. 10). It would
take a full-sized essay in itself to unscramble, let alone refute, this absurd
balderdash, in which a few truths are either mixed with or coated in sheer
fantasy. Bradford bases his account, we are told, on 'greater access to the views
of primal people and their native descendants' by 'a more critical . . .
anthropology' (CIB, p. 10). In fact, much of his 'critical anthropology' appears
to derive from ideas propounded at the 'Man the Hunter' symposium, convened in
April 1966 at the University of Chicago. [16] Although most of the papers
contributed to this symposium were immensely valuable, a number of them conformed
to the naive mystification of 'primitivity' that was percolating through the
1960s counterculture -- and that lingers on to this day. The hippie culture,
which influenced quite a few anthropologists of the time, averred that
hunting-gathering peoples today had been bypassed by the social and economic
forces at work in the rest of the world and still lived in a pristine state, as
isolated remnants of Neolithic and Paleolithic lifeways. Further, as
hunter-gatherers, their lives were notably healthy and peaceful, living then as
now on an ample natural largess. Thus, Richard B. Lee, coeditor of the
collection of conference papers, estimated that the caloric intake of 'primitive'
peoples was quite high and their food supply abundant, making for a kind of
virginal 'affluence' in which people needed to forage only a few hours each day.
'Life in the state of nature is not necessarily nasty, brutish, and short,' wrote
Lee. The habitat of the !Kung Bushmen of the Kalahari Desert, for example, 'is
abundant in naturally occurring foods.' The Bushmen of the Dobe area, who, Lee
wrote, were still on the verge of entry into the Neolithic, live well today
on wild plants and meat, in spite of the fact that they are confined to the least
productive portion of the range in which Bushmen peoples were formerly found. It
is likely that an even more substantial subsistence base would have been
characteristic of these hunters and gatherers in the past, when they had the pick
of African habitats to choose from. [17] Not quite! -- as we shall see
shortly. It is all too common for those who swoon over 'primal life' to lump
together many millennia of prehistory, as if significantly different hominid and
human species lived in one kind of social organization. The word prehistory is
highly ambiguous. Inasmuch as the human genus included several different species,
we can hardly equate the 'outlook' of Aurignacian and Magdalenian foragers (Homo
sapiens sapiens) some 30,000 years ago, with that of Homo sapiens
neanderthalensis or Homo erectus, whose tool kits, artistic abilities, and
capacities for speech were strikingly different. Another concern is the
extent to which prehistoric hunter-gatherers or foragers at various times lived
in nonhierarchical societies. If the burials at Sungir (in present Eastern
Europe) some 25,000 years ago allow for any speculation (and there are no
Paleolithic people around to tell us about their lives), the extraordinarily rich
collection of jewelry, lances, ivory spears, and beaded clothing at the
gravesites of two adolescents suggest the existence of high-status family lines
long before human beings settled down to food cultivation. Most cultures in the
Paleolithic were probably relatively egalitarian, but hierarchy seems to have
existed even in the late Paleolithic, with marked variations in degree, type, and
scope of domination that cannot be subsumed under rhetorical paeans to
Paleolithic egalitarianism. A further concern that arises is the variation --
in early cases, the absence -- of communicative ability in different epochs.
Inasmuch as a written language did not appear until well into historical times,
the languages even of early Homo sapiens sapiens were hardly 'conceptually
profound.' The pictographs, glyphs, and, above all, memorized material upon which
'primal' peoples relied for knowledge of the past have obvious cultural
limitations. Without a written literature that records the cumulative wisdom of
generations, historical memory, let alone 'conceptually profound' thoughts, are
difficult to retain; rather, they are lost over time or woefully distorted. Least
of all is orally transmitted history subject to demanding critique but instead
easily becomes a tool for elite 'seers' and shamans who, far from being
'protopoets,' as Bradford calls them, seem to have used their 'knowledge' to
serve their own social interests. [18] Which brings us, inevitably, to John
Zerzan, the anti'civiliza'tional primitivist par excellence. For Zerzan, one of
the steady hands at Anarchy: A Journal of Desire Armed, the absence of speech,
language, and writing is a positive boon. Another denizen of the 'Man the Hunter'
time warp, Zerzan maintains in his book Future Primitive (FP) that 'life before
domestication/agriculture was in fact largely one of a leisure, intimacy with
nature, sensual wisdom, sexual equality, and health' [19] -- with the difference
that Zerzan's vision of 'primality' more closely approximates four-legged
animality. In fact, in Zerzanian paleoanthropology, the anatomical distinctions
between Homo sapiens, on the one hand, and Homo habilis, Homo erectus, and the
'much-maligned' Neanderthals, on the other, are dubious; all early Homo species,
in his view, were possessed of the mental and physical capacities of Homo sapiens
and furthermore lived in primal bliss for more than two million years. If
these hominids were as intelligent as modern humans, we may be naively tempted to
ask, why did they not innovate tech'no'logical change? 'It strikes me as very
plausible,' Zerzan brightly conjectures, 'that intelligence, informed by the
success and satisfaction of a gatherer-hunter existence, is the very reason for
the pronounced absence of 'progress.' Division of labor, domestication, symbolic
culture -- these were evidently [!] refused until very recently.' The Homo
species 'long chose nature over culture,' and by culture here Zerzan means 'the
manipulation of basic symbolic forms' (emphasis added) -- an alienating
encumbrance. Indeed, he continues, 'reified time, language (written, certainly,
and probably spoken language for all or most of this period), number, and art had
no place, despite an intelligence fully capable of them' (FP, pp. 23, 24). In
short, hominids were capable of symbols, speech, and writing but deliberately
rejected them, since they could understand one another and their environment
instinctively, without recourse to them. Thus Zerzan eagerly agrees with an
anthropologist who meditates that 'San/Bushman communion with nature' reached 'a
level of experience that 'could almost be called mystical. For instance, they
seemed to know what it actually felt like to be an elephant, a lion, an
antelope'' even a baobab tree (FP, pp. 33-34). The conscious 'decision' to
refuse language, sophisticated tools, temporality, and a division of labor
(presumably they tried and grunted, 'Bah!') was made, we are told, by Homo
habilis, who, I should note, had roughly half the brain size of modern humans and
probably lacked the anatomical capacity for syllabic speech. Yet we have it on
Zerzan's sovereign authority that habilis (and possibly even Australopithecus
afarensis, who may have been around some 'two million years ago') possessed 'an
intelligence fully capable' -- no less! -- of these functions but refused to use
them. In Zerzanian paleoanthropology, early hominids or humans could adopt or
reject vital cultural traits like speech with sublime wisdom, the way monks take
vows of silence. But once the vow of silence was broken, everything went
wrong! For reasons known only to God and Zerzan, The emergence of symbolic
culture, with its inherent will to manipulate and control, soon opened the door
to the domestication of nature. After two million years of human life within the
bounds of nature, in balance with other wild species, agriculture changed our
lifestyle, our way of adapting, in an unprecedented way. Never before has such a
radical change occurred in a species so utterly and so swiftly. . . .
Self-domestication through language, ritual, and art inspired the taming of
plants and animals that followed. (FP, pp. 27-28, emphasis added) There is a
certain splendor in this claptrap that is truly arresting. Significantly
different epochs, hominid and/or human species, and ecological and technological
situations are all swept up together into a shared life 'within the bounds of
nature.' Zerzan's simplification of the highly complex dialectic between humans
and nonhuman nature reveals a mentality so reductionist and simplistic that one
is obliged to stand before it in awe. To be sure, there is very much we can
learn from preliterate cultures -- organic societies, as I call them in The
Ecology of Freedom -- particularly about the mutability of what is commonly
called 'human nature.' Their spirit of in-group cooperation and, in the best of
cases, egalitarian outlook are not only admirable -- and socially necessary in
view of the precarious world in which they lived -- but provide compelling
evidence of the malleability of human behavior in contrast to the myth that
competition and greed are innate human attributes. Indeed, their practices of
usufruct and the inequality of equals are of great relevance to an ecological
society. But that 'primal' or prehistoric peoples 'revered' nonhuman nature
is at best specious and at worst completely disingenuous. In the absence of
'nonnatural' environments such as villages, towns, and cities, the very notion of
'Nature' as distinguished from habitat had yet to be conceptualized -- a truly
alienating experience, in Zerzan's view. Nor is it likely that our remote
ancestors viewed the natural world in a manner any less instrumental than did
people in historical cultures. With due regard for their own material interests
-- their survival and well-being -- prehistoric peoples seem to have hunted down
as much game as they could, and if they imaginatively peopled the animal world
with anthropomorphic attributes, as they surely did, it would have been to
communicate with it with an end toward manipulating it, not simply toward
revering it. Thus, with very instrumental ends in mind, they conjured
'talking' animals, animal 'tribes' (often patterned on their own social
structures), and responsive animal 'spirits.' Understandably, given their limited
knowledge, they believed in the reality of dreams, where humans might fly and
animals might talk -- in an inexplicable, often frightening dream world that they
took for reality. To control game animals, to use a habitat for survival
purposes, to deal with the vicissitudes of weather and the like, prehistoric
peoples had to personify these phenomena and 'talk' to them, whether directly,
ritualistically, or metaphorically. In fact, prehistoric peoples seem to have
intervened into their environment as resolutely as they could. As soon as Homo
erectus or later human species learned to use fire, for example, they seem to
have put it to work burning off forests, probably stampeding game animals over
cliffs or into natural enclosures where they could be easily slaughtered. The
'reverence for life' of prehistoric peoples thus reflected a highly pragmatic
concern for enhancing and controlling the food supply, not a love for animals,
forests, mountains (which they may very well have feared as the lofty home of
deities both demonic and benign). [20] Nor does the 'love of nature' that
Bradford attributes to 'primal society' accurately depict foraging peoples today,
who often deal rather harshly with work and game animals; the Ituri forest
Pygmies, for example, tormented ensnared game quite sadistically, and Eskimos
commonly maltreated their huskies. [21] As for Native Americans before European
contact, they vastly altered much of the continent by using fire to clear lands
for horticulture and for better visibility in hunting, to the extent that the
'paradise' encountered by Europeans was 'clearly humanized.' [22]
Unavoidably, many Indian tribes seem to have exhausted local food animals and had
to migrate to new territories to gain the material means of life. It would be
surprising indeed if they did not engage in warfare to displace the original
occupants. Their remote ancestors may well have pushed some of the great North
American mammals of the last ice age (notably mammoths, mastodons, longhorn
bison, horses, and camels) to extinction. Thickly accumulated bones of bison are
still discernible in sites that suggest mass killings and 'assembly-line'
butchering in a number of American arroyos. [23] Nor, among those peoples who
did have agriculture, was land use necessarily ecologically benign. Around Lake
P'tzcuaro in the central Mexican highlands, before the Spanish conquest,
'prehistoric land use was not conservationist in practice,' writes Karl W.
Butzer, but caused high rates of soil erosion. Indeed, aboriginal farming
practices 'could be as damaging as any pre-industrial land-use in the Old World.'
[24] Other studies have shown that forest overclearing and the failure of
subsistence agriculture undermined Mayan society and contributed to its collapse.
[25] We will never have any way of knowing whether the lifeways of today's
foraging cultures accurately mirror those of our ancestral past. Not only did
modern aboriginal cultures develop over thousands of years, but they were
significantly altered by the diffusion of countless traits from other cultures
before they were studied by Western researchers. Indeed, as Clifford Geertz has
observed rather acidly, there is little if anything pristine about the aboriginal
cultures that modern primitivists associate with early humanity. 'The
realization, grudging and belated, that [the pristine primality of existing
aborigines] is not so, not even with the Pygmies, not even with the Eskimos,'
Geertz observes, 'and that these people are in fact products of larger-scale
processes of social change which have made them and continue to make them what
they are -- has come as something of a shock that has induced a virtual crisis in
the field [of ethnography].' [26] Scores of 'primal' peoples, like the forests
they inhabited, were no more 'virginal' at European contact than were the Lakota
Indians at the time of the American Civil War, Dancing With Wolves to the
contrary notwithstanding. Many of the much-touted 'primal' belief-systems of
existing aborigines are clearly traceable to Christian influences. Black Elk, for
example, was a zealous Catholic, [27] while the late-nineteenth-century Ghost
Dance of the Paiute and Lakota was profoundly influenced by Christian evangelical
millennarianism. In serious anthropological research, the notion of an
'ecstatic,' pristine hunter has not survived the thirty years that have passed
since the 'Man the Hunter' symposium. Most of the 'affluent hunter' societies
cited by devotees of the myth of 'primitive affluence' literally devolved --
probably very much against their desires -- from horticultural social systems.
The San people of the Kalahari are now known to have been gardeners before they
were driven into the desert. Several hundred years ago, according to Edwin
Wilmsen, San-speaking peoples were herding and farming, not to speak of trading
with neighboring agricultural chiefdoms in a network that extended to the Indian
Ocean. By the year 1000, excavations have shown, their area, Dobe, was populated
by people who made ceramics, worked with iron, and herded cattle, exporting them
to Europe by the 1840s together with massive amounts of ivory -- much of it from
elephants hunted by the San people themselves, who doubtless conducted this
slaughter of their pachyderm 'brothers' with the great sensitivity that Zerzan
attributes to them. The marginal foraging lifeways of the San that so entranced
observers in the 1960s were actually the result of economic changes in the late
nineteenth century, while 'the remoteness imagined by outside observers . . . was
not indigenous but was created by the collapse of mercantile capital.' [28] Thus,
'the current status of San-speaking peoples on the rural fringe of African
economies,' Wilmsen notes, can be accounted for only in terms of the social
policies and economies of the colonial era and its aftermath. Their appearance as
foragers is a function of their relegation to an underclass in the playing out of
historical processes that began before the current millennium and culminated in
the early decades of this century. [29] The Yuqu' of the Amazon, too, could
easily have epitomized the pristine foraging society extolled in the 1960s.
Unstudied by Europeans until the 1950s, this people had a tool kit that consisted
of little more than a boar claw and bow-and-arrows: 'In addition to being unable
to produce fire,' writes Allyn M. Stearman, who studied them, 'they had no
watercraft, no domestic animals (not even the dog), no stone, no ritual
specialists, and only a rudimentarycosmology. They lived out their lives as
nomads, wandering the forests of lowland Bolivia in search of game and other
foods provided by their foraging skills.' [30] They grew no crops at all and were
unfamiliar with the use of the hook and line for fishing. Yet far from being
egalitarian, the Yuqu' maintained the institution of hereditary slavery, dividing
their society into a privileged elite stratum and a scorned laboring slave group.
This feature is now regarded as a vestige of former horticultural lifeways. The
Yuqu', it appears, were descended from a slave-holding pre-Columbian society, and
'over time, they experienced deculturation, losing much of their cultural
heritage as it became necessary to remain mobile and live off the land. But while
many elements of their culture may have been lost, others were not. Slavery,
evidently, was one of these.'[31] Not only has the myth of the 'pristine'
forager been shattered, but Richard Lee's own data on the caloric intake of
'affluent' foragers have been significantly challenged by Wilmsen and his
associates. [32] !Kung people had average lifespans of about thirty years. Infant
mortality was high, and according to Wilmsen (pace Bradford!), the people were
subject to disease and hunger during lean seasons. (Lee himself has revised his
views on this score since the 1960s.) Correspondingly, the lives of our early
ancestors were most certainly anything but blissful. In fact, life for them was
actually quite harsh, generally short, and materially very demanding. Anatomical
assays of their longevity show that about half died in childhood or before the
age of twenty, and few lived beyond their fiftieth year. They were more likely
scavengers than hunter-gatherers and were probably prey for leopards and hyenas.
[33] To members of their own bands, tribes, or clans, prehistoric and later
foraging peoples were normally cooperative and peaceful; but toward members of
other bands, tribes, or clans, they were often warlike, even sometimes genocidal
in their efforts to dispossess them and appropriate their land. That most
blissed-out of ancestral humans (if we are to believe the primitivists), Homo
erectus, has left behind a bleak record of interhuman slaughter, according to
data summarized by Paul Janssens. [34] It has been suggested that many
individuals in China and Java were killed by volcanic eruptions, but the latter
explanations loses a good deal of plausibility in the light of the remains of
forty individuals whose mortally injured heads were decapitated -- 'hardly the
action of a volcano,' Corinne Shear Wood observes dryly. [35] As to modern
foragers, the conflicts between Native American tribes are too numerous to cite
at any great length -- as witness the Anasazi and their neighbors in the
Southwest, the tribes that were to finally make up the Iroquois Confederacy (the
Confederacy itself was a matter of survival if they were not to all but
exterminate one another), and the unrelenting conflict between Mohawks and
Hurons, which led to the near extermination and flight of remanent Huron
communities. If the 'desires' of prehistoric peoples 'were easily met,' as
Bradford alleges, it was precisely because their material conditions of life --
and hence their desires -- were very simple indeed. Such might be expected of any
life-form that largely adapts rather than innovates, that conforms to its
pregiven habitat rather than alters it to make that habitat conform with its own
wants. To be sure, early peoples had a marvelous understanding of the habitat in
which they lived; they were, after all, highly intelligent and imaginative
beings. Yet their 'ecstatic' culture was unavoidably riddled not only by joy and
'singing . . . celebrating . . . dreaming,' but by superstition and easily
'manipulable fears. Neither our remote ancestors nor existing aborigines
could have survived if they held the 'enchanted' Disneyland ideas imputed to them
by present-day primitivists. Certainly, Europeans offered aboriginal peoples no
magnificent social dispensation. Quite to the contrary: imperialists subjected
native peoples to crass exploitation, outright genocide, diseases against which
they had no immunity, and shameless plunder. No animistic conjurations did or
could have prevented this onslaught, as at the tragedy of Wounded Knee in 1890,
where the myth of ghost shirts impregnable to bullets was so painfully
belied. What is of crucial importance is that the regression to primitivism
among lifestyle anarchists denies the most salient attributes of humanity as a
species and the potentially emancipatory aspects of Euro-American civilization.
Humans are vastly different from other animals in that they do more than merely
adapt to the world around them; they innovate and create a new world, not only to
discover their own powers as human beings but to make the world around them more
suitable for their own development, both as individuals and as a species. Warped
as this capacity is by the present irrational society, the ability to change the
world is a natural endowment, the product of human biological evolution -- not
simply a product of technology, rationality, and civilization. That people who
call themselves anarchists should advance a primitivism that verges on the
animalistic, with its barely concealed message of adaptiveness and passivity,
sullies centuries of revolutionary thought, ideals, and practice, indeed defames
the memorable efforts of humanity to free itself from parochialism, mysticism,
and superstition and change the world. For lifestyle anarchists, particularly
of the anticivilizational and primitivistic genre, history itself becomes a
degrading monolith that swallows up all distinctions, mediations, phases of
development, and social specificities. Capitalism and its contradictions are
reduced to epiphenomena of an all-devouring civilization and its technological
'imperatives' that lack nuance and differentiation. History, insofar as we
conceive it as the unfolding of humanity's rational component -- its developing
potentiality for freedom, self-consciousness, and cooperation -- is a complex
account of the cultivation of human sensibilities, institutions, intellectuality,
and knowledge, or what was once called 'the education of humanity.' To deal with
history as a steady 'Fall' from an animalistic 'authenticity,' as Zerzan,
Bradford, and their compatriots do in varying degrees in a fashion very similar
to that of Martin Heidegger, is to ignore the expanding ideals of freedom,
individuality, and self-consciousness that have marked epochs of human
development -- not to speak of the widening scope of the revolutionary struggles
to achieve these ends. Anticivilizational lifestyle anarchism is merely one
aspect of the social regression that marks the closing decades of the twentieth
century. Just as capitalism threatens to unravel natural history by bringing it
back to a simpler, less differentiated geological and zoological era, so
anticivilizational lifestyle anarchism is complicit with capitalism in bringing
the human spirit and its history back to a less developed, less determinate,
pre'lapsarian world -- the supposedly 'innocent' pretechnological and
precivilizatory society that existed before humanity's 'fall from grace.' Like
the Lotus Eaters in Homer's Odyssey, humans are 'authentic' when they live in an
eternal present, without past or future -- untroubled by memory or ideation, free
of tradition, and unchallenged by becoming. Ironically, the world idealized
by primitivists would actually preclude the radical individualism celebrated by
the individualist heirs of Max Stirner. Although contemporary 'primal'
communities have produced strongly etched individuals, the power of custom and
the high degree of group solidarity impelled by demanding conditions allow little
leeway for expansively individualistic behavior, of the kind demanded by
Stirnerite anarchists who celebrate the supremacy of the ego. Today, dabbling in
primitivism is precisely the privilege of affluent urbanites who can afford to
toy with fantasies denied not only to the hungry and poor and to the 'nomads' who
by necessity inhabit urban streets but to the overworked employed. Modern working
women with children could hardly do without washing machines to relieve them,
however minimally, from their daily domestic labors -- before going to work to
earn what is often the greater part of their households' income. Ironically, even
the collective that produces Fifth Estate found it could not do without a
computer and was 'forced' to purchase one -- issuing the disingenuous disclaimer,
'We hate it!' [36] Denouncing an advanced technology while using it to generate
antitechnological literature is not only disingenuous but has sanctimonious
dimensions: Such 'hatred' of computers seems more like the belch of the
privileged, who, having overstuffed themselves with delicacies, extol the virtues
of poverty during Sunday prayers. Evaluating Lifestyle Anarchism
What stands out most compellingly in today's lifestyle anarchism is its appetite
for immediacy rather than reflection, for a naive one-to-one relationship between
mind and reality. Not only does this immediacy immunize libertarian thinking from
demands for nuanced and mediated reflection; it precludes rational analysis and,
for that matter, rationality itself. Consigning humanity to the nontemporal,
nonspatial, and nonhistorical -- a 'primal' notion of temporality based on the
'eternal' cycles of 'Nature' -- it thereby divests mind of its creative
uniqueness and its freedom to intervene into the natural world. >From the
standpoint of primitivist lifestyle anarchism, human beings are at their best
when they adapt to nonhuman nature rather than intervene in it, or when,
disencumbered of reason, technology, civilization, and even speech, they live in
placid 'harmony' with existing reality, perhaps endowed with 'natural rights,' in
a visceral and essentially mindless 'ecstatic' condition. T.A.Z., Fifth Estate,
Anarchy: A Journal of Desire Armed, and lumpen 'zines' like Michael William's
Stirnerite Demolition Derby -- all focus on an unmediated, ahistorical, and
anticivilizatory 'primality' from which we have 'fallen,' a state of perfection
and 'authenticity' in which we were guided variously by the 'bounds of nature,'
'natural law,' or our devouring egos. History and civilization consist of nothing
but a descent into the inauthenticity of 'industrial society.' As I have
already suggested, this mythos of a 'falling from authenticity' has its roots in
reactionary romanticism, most recently in the philosophy of Martin Heidegger,
whose v'lkisch 'spiritualism,' latent in Being and Time, later emerged in his
explicitly fascist works. This view now feeds on the quietistic mysticism that
abounds in the antidemocratic writings of Rudolf Bahro, with its barely disguised
appeal for 'salvation' by a 'Green Adolf,' and in the apolitical quest for
ecological spiritualism and 'self-fulfillment' propounded by deep ecologists.
In the end, the individual ego becomes the supreme temple of reality, excluding
history and becoming, democracy and responsibility. Indeed, lived contact with
society as such is rendered tenuous by a narcissism so all-embracing that it
shrivels consociation to an infantilized ego that is little more than a bundle of
shrieking demands and claims for its own satisfactions. Civilization merely
obstructs the ecstatic self-realization of this ego's desires, reified as the
ultimate fulfillment of emancipation, as though ecstasy and desire were not
products of cultivation and historical development, but merely innate impulses
that appear ab novo in a desocialized world. Like the petty-bourgeois
Stirnerite ego, primitivist lifestyle anarchism allows no room for social
institutions, political organizations, and radical programs, still less a public
sphere, which all the writers we have examined automatically identify with
statecraft. The sporadic, the unsystematic, the incoherent, the discontinuous,
and the intuitive supplant the consistent, purposive, organized, and rational,
indeed any form of sustained and focused activity apart from publishing a 'zine'
or pamphlet -- or burning a garbage can. Imagination is counterposed to reason
and desire to theoretical coherence, as though the two were in radical
contradiction to each other. Goya's admonition that imagination without reason
produces monsters is altered to leave the impression that imagination flourishes
on an unmediated experience with an unnuanced 'oneness.' Thus is social nature
essentially dissolved into biological nature; innovative humanity, into adaptive
animality; temporality, into precivilizatory eternality; history, into an archaic
cyclicity. A bourgeois reality whose economic harshness grows starker and
crasser with every passing day is shrewdly mutated by lifestyle anarchism into
constellations of self-indulgence, inchoateness, indiscipline, and incoherence.
In the 1960s, the Situationists, in the name of a 'theory of the spectacle,' in
fact produced a reified spectacle of the theory, but they at least offered
organizational correctives, such as workers' councils, that gave their
aestheticism some ballast. Lifestyle anarchism, by assailing organization,
programmatic commitment, and serious social analysis, apes the worst aspects of
Situationist aestheticism without adhering to the project of building a movement.
As the detritus of the 1960s, it wanders aimlessly within the bounds of the ego
(renamed by Zerzan the 'bounds of nature') and makes a virtue of bohemian
incoherence. What is most troubling is that the self-indulgent aesthetic
vagaries of lifestyle anarchism significantly erode the socialist core of a
left-libertarian ideology that once could claim social relevance and weight
precisely for its uncompromising commitment to emancipation -- not outside of
history, in the realm of the subjective, but within history, in the realm of the
objective. The great cry of the First International -- which anarcho-syndicalism
and anarchocommunism retained after Marx and his supporters abandoned it -- was
the demand: 'No rights without duties, no duties without rights.' For
generations, this slogan adorned the mastheads of what we must now
retrospectively call social anarchist periodicals. Today, it stands radically at
odds with the basically egocentric demand for 'desire armed,' and with Taoist
contemplation and Buddhist nirvanas. Where social anarchism called upon people to
rise in revolution and seek the reconstruction of society, the irate petty
bourgeois who populate the subcultural world of lifestyle anarchism call for
episodic rebellion and the satisfaction of their 'desiring machines,' to use the
phraseology of Deleuze and Guattari. The steady retreat from the historic
commitment of classical anarchism to social struggle (without which
self-realization and the fulfillment of desire in all its dimensions, not merely
the instinctive, cannot be achieved) is inevitably accompanied by a disastrous
mystification of experience and reality. The ego, identified almost
fetishistically as the locus of emancipation, turns out to be identical to the
'sovereign individual' of laissez-faire individualism. Detached from its social
moorings, it achieves not autonomy but the heteronomous 'selfhood' of
petty-bourgeois enterprise. Indeed, far from being free, the ego in its
sovereign selfhood is bound hand and foot to the seemingly anonymous laws of the
marketplace -- the laws of competition and exploitation -- which render the myth
of individual freedom into another fetish concealing the implacable laws of
capital accumulation. Lifestyle anarchism, in effect, turns out to be an
additional mystifying bourgeois deception. Its acolytes are no more 'autonomous'
than the movements of the stock market, than price fluctuations and the mundane
facts of bourgeois commerce. All claims to autonomy notwithstanding, this
middle-class 'rebel,' with or without a brick in hand, is entirely captive to the
subterranean market forces that occupy all the allegedly 'free' terrains of
modern social life, from food cooperatives to rural communes. Capitalism
swirls around us -- not only materially but culturally. As John Zerzan so
memorably put it to a puzzled interviewer who asked about the television set in
the home of this foe of technology: 'Like all other people, I have to be
narcotized.'[37] That lifestyle anarchism itself is a 'narcotizing'
self-deception can best be seen in Max Stirner's The Ego and His Own, where the
ego's claim to 'uniqueness' in the temple of the sacrosanct 'self' far outranks
John Stuart Mill's liberal pieties. Indeed, with Stirner, egoism becomes a matter
of epistemology. Cutting through the maze of contradictions and woefully
incomplete statements that fill The Ego and His Own, one finds Stirner's 'unique'
ego to be a myth because its roots lie in its seeming 'other' -- society itself.
Indeed: 'Truth cannot step forward as you do,' Stirner addresses the egoist,
'cannot move, change, develop; truth awaits and recruits everything from you, and
itself is only through you; for it exists only -- in your head.'[38] The
Stirnerite egoist, in effect, bids farewell to objective reality, to the
facticity of the social, and thereby to fundamental social change and all ethical
criteria and ideals beyond personal satisfaction amidst the hidden demons of the
bourgeois marketplace. This absence of mediation subverts the very existence of
the concrete, not to speak of the authority of the Stirnerite ego itself -- a
claim so all-encompassing as to exclude the social roots of the self and its
formation in history. Nietzsche, quite independently of Stirner, carried this
view of truth to its logical conclusion by erasing the facticity and reality of
truth as such: 'What, then, is truth?' he asked. 'A mobile army of metaphors,
metonyms, and anthropomorphisms -- in short, a sum of human relations, which have
been enhanced, transposed, and embellished poetically and rhetorically.' [39]
With more forthrightness than Stirner, Nietzsche contended that facts are simply
interpretations; indeed, he asked, 'is it necessary to posit an interpreter
behind the interpretations?' Apparently not, for 'even this is invention,
hypothesis.' [40] Following Nietzsche's unrelenting logic, we are left with a
self that not only essentially creates it own reality but also must justify its
own existence as more than a mere interpretation. Such egoism thus annihilates
the ego itself, which vanishes into the mist of Stirner's own unstated
premises. Similarly divested of history, society, and facticity beyond its
own 'metaphors,' lifestyle anarchism lives in an asocial domain in which the ego,
with its cryptic desires, must evaporate into logical abstractions. But reducing
the ego to intuitive immediacy -- anchoring it in mere animality, in the 'bounds
of nature,' or in 'natural law' -- would amount to ignoring the fact that the ego
is the product of an ever-formative history, indeed, a history that, if it is to
consist of more than mere episodes, must avail itself of reason as a guide to
standards of progress and regress, necessity and freedom, good and evil, and --
yes! -- civilization and barbarism. Indeed, an anarchism that seeks to avoid the
shoals of sheer solipsism on the one hand and the loss of the 'self' as a mere
'interpretation' one the other must become explicitly socialist or collectivist.
That is to say, it must be a social anarchism that seeks freedom through
structure and mutual responsibility, not through a vaporous, nomadic ego that
eschews the preconditions for social life. Stated bluntly: Between the
socialist pedigree of anarcho-syndicalism and anarchocommunism (which have never
denied the importance of self-realization and the fulfillment of desire), and the
basically liberal, individualistic pedigree of lifestyle anarchism (which fosters
social ineffectuality, if not outright social negation), there exits a divide
that cannot be bridged unless we completely disregard the profoundly different
goals, methods, and underlying philosophy that distinguish them. Stirner's own
project, in fact, emerged in a debate with the socialism of Wilhelm Weitling and
Moses Hess, where he invoked egoism precisely to counterpose to socialism.
'Personal insurrection rather than general revolution was [Stirner's] message,'
James J. Martin admiringly observes [41] -- a counterposition that lives on today
in lifestyle anarchism and its yuppie filiations, as distinguished from social
anarchism with its roots in historicism, the social matrix of individuality, and
its commitment to a rational society. The very incongruity of these
essentially mixed messages, which coexist on every page of the lifestyle 'zines,'
reflects the feverish voice of the squirming petty bourgeois. If anarchism loses
its socialist core and collectivist goal, if it drifts off into aestheticism,
ecstasy, and desire, and, incongruously, into Taoist quietism and Buddhist
self-effacement as a substitute for a libertarian program, politics, and
organization, it will come to represent not social regeneration and a
revolutionary vision but social decay and a petulant egoistic rebellion. Worse,
it will feed the wave of mysticism that is already sweeping affluent members of
the generation now in their teens and twenties. Lifestyle anarchism's exaltation
of ecstasy, certainly laudable in a radical social matrix but here unabashedly
intermingled with 'sorcery,' is producing a dreamlike absorption with spirits,
ghosts, and Jungian archetypes rather than a rational and dialectical awareness
of the world. Characteristically, the cover of a recent issue of Alternative
Press Review (Fall 1994), a widely read American feral anarchist periodical, is
adorned with a three-headed Buddhist deity in serene nirvanic repose, against a
presumably cosmic background of swirling galaxies and New Age paraphernalia -- an
image that could easily join Fifth Estate's 'Anarchy' poster in a New Age
boutique. Inside thecover, a graphic cries out: 'Life Can Be Magic When We Start
to Break Free' (the A in Magic is circled) -- to which one is obliged to ask:
How? With what? The magazine itself contains a deep ecology essay by Glenn Parton
(drawn from David Foreman's periodical Wild Earth) titled: 'The Wild Self: Why I
Am a Primitivist,' extolling 'primitive peoples' whose 'way of life fits into the
pre-given natural world,' lamenting the Neolithic revolution, and identifying our
'primary task' as being to ''unbuild' our civilization, and restore wilderness.'
The magazine's artwork celebrates vulgarity -- human skulls and images of ruins
are very much in evidence. Its lengthiest contribution, 'Decadence,' reprinted
from Black Eye, melds the romantic with the lumpen, exultantly concluding: 'It's
time for a real Roman holiday, so bring on the barbarians!' Alas, the
barbarians are already here -- and the 'Roman holiday' in today's American cities
flourishes on crack, thuggery, insensitivity, stupidity, primitivism,
anticivilizationism, antirationalism, and a sizable dose of 'anarchy' conceived
as chaos. Lifestyle anarchism must be seen in the present social context not only
of demoralized black ghettoes and reactionary white suburbs but even of Indian
reservations, those ostensible centers of 'primality,' in which gangs of Indian
youths now shoot at one another, drug dealing is rampant, and 'gang graffiti
greets visitors even at the sacred Window Rock monument,' as Seth Mydans reports
in The New York Times (March 3, 1995). Thus, a widespread cultural decay has
followed the degeneration of the 1960s New Left into postmodernism and of its
counter'culture into New Age spiritualism. For timid lifestyle anarchists,
Halloween artwork and incendiary articles push hope and an understanding of
reality into the ever-receding distance. Torn by the lures of 'cultural
terrorism' and Buddhist ashrams, lifestyle anarchists in fact find themselves in
a crossfire between the barbarians at the top of society in Wall Street and the
City, and those at its bottom, in the dismal urban ghettoes of Euro-America.
Alas, the conflict in which they find themselves, for all their celebrations of
lumpen lifeways (to which corporate barbarians are no strangers these days) has
less to do with the need to create a free society than with a brutal war over who
is to share in the in the available spoils from the sale of drugs, human bodies,
exorbitant loans -- and let us not forget junk bonds and international
currencies. A return to mere animality -- or shall we call it
'decivilization'? -- is a return not to freedom but to instinct, to the domain of
'authenticity' that is guided more by genes than by brains. Nothing could be
further from the ideals of freedom spelled out in ever-expansive forms by the
great revolutions of the past. And nothing could be more unrelenting in its sheer
obedience to biochemical imperatives such as DNA or more in contrast to the
creativity, ethics, and mutuality opened by culture and struggles for a rational
civilization. There is no freedom in 'wildness' if, by sheer ferality, we mean
the dictates of inborn behavioral patterns that shape mere animality. To malign
civilization without due recognition of its enormous potentialities for
self-conscious freedom -- a freedom conferred by reason as well as emotion, by
insight as well as desire, by prose as well as poetry -- is to retreat back into
the shadowy world of brutishness, when thought was dim and intellectuation was
only an evolutionary promise. Toward a Democratic Communalism
My
picture of lifestyle anarchism is far from complete; the personalistic thrust of
this ideological clay allows it to be molded in many forms provided that words
like imagination, sacred, intuitive, ecstasy, and primal embellish its
surface. Social anarchism, in my view, is made of fundamentally different
stuff, heir to the Enlightenment tradition, with due regard to that tradition's
limits and incompleteness. Depending upon how it defines reason, social anarchism
celebrates the thinking human mind without in any way denying passion, ecstasy,
imagination, play, and art. Yet rather than reify them into hazy categories, it
tries to incorporate them into everyday life. It is committed to rationality
while opposing the rationalization of experience; to technology, while opposing
the 'megamachine'; to social institutionalization, while opposing class rule and
hierarchy; to a genuine politics based on the confederal coordination of
municipalities or communes by the people in direct face-to-face democracy, while
opposing parliamentarism and the state. This 'Commune of communes,' to use a
traditional slogan of earlier revolutions, can be appropriately designated as
Communalism. Opponents of democracy as 'rule' to the contrary notwithstanding, it
describes the democratic dimension of anarchism as a majoritarian administration
of the public sphere. Accordingly, Communalism seeks freedom rather than autonomy
in the sense that I have counterposed them. It sharply breaks with the
psycho-personal Stirnerite, liberal, and bohemian ego as a self-contained
sovereign by asserting that individuality does not emerge ab novo, dressed at
birth in 'natural rights,' but sees individuality in great part as the
ever-changing work of historical and social development, a process of
self-formation that can be neither petrified by biologism nor arrested by
temporally limited dogmas. The sovereign, self-sufficient 'individual' has
always been a precarious basis upon which to anchor a left libertarian outlook.
As Max Horkheimer once observed, 'individuality is impaired when each man decides
to fend for himself. . . . The absolutely isolated individual has always been an
illusion. The most esteemed personal qualities, such as independence, will to
freedom, sympathy, and the sense of justice, are social as well as individual
virtues. The fully developed individual is the consummation of a fully developed
society.'[42] If a left-libertarian vision of a future society is not to
disappear in a bohemian and lumpen demimonde, it must offer a resolution to
social problems, not flit arrogantly from slogan to slogan, shielding itself from
rationality with bad poetry and vulgar graphics. Democracy is not antithetical to
anarchism; nor are majority rule and nonconsensual decisions incommensurable with
a libertarian society. That no society can exist without institutional
structures is transparently clear to anyone who has not been stupefied by Stirner
and his kind. By denying institutions and democracy, lifestyle anarchism
insulates itself from social reality, so that it can fume all the more with
futile rage, thereby remaining a subcultural caper for gullible youth and bored
consumers of black garments and ecstasy posters. To argue that democracy and
anarchism are incompatible because any impediment to the wishes of even 'a
minority of one' constitutes a violation of personal autonomy is to advocate not
a free society but Brown's 'collection of individuals' -- in short, a herd. No
longer would 'imagination' come to 'power.' Power, which always exists, will
belong either to the collective in a face-to-face and clearly institutionalized
democracy, or to the egos of a few oligarchs who will produce a 'tyranny of
structurelessness.' Not unjustifiably, Kropotkin, in his Encyclopaedia
Britannica article, regarded the Stirnerite ego as elitist and deprecated it as
hierarchical. Approvingly, he cited V. Basch's criticism of Stirner's individual
anarchism as a form of elitism, maintaining 'that the aim of all superior
civilization is, not to permit all members of the community to develop in a
normal way, but to permit certain better endowed individuals 'fully to develop,'
even at the cost of the happiness and the very existence of the mass of mankind.'
In anarchism, this produces, in effect, a regression toward the most common
individualism, advocated by all the would-be superior minorities to which indeed
man owes in his history precisely the State and the rest, which these
individualists combat. Their individualism goes so far as to end in a negation of
their own starting-point -- to say nothing of the impossibility of the individual
to attain a really full development in the conditions of oppression of the masses
by the 'beautiful aristocracies.'[43] In its amoralism, this elitism easily
lends itself to the unfreedom of the 'masses' by ultimately placing them in the
custody of the 'unique ones,' a logic that may yield a leadership principle
characteristic of fascist ideology.[44] In the United States and much of
Europe, precisely at a time when mass disillusionment with the state has reached
unprecedented proportions, anarchism is in retreat. Dissatisfaction with
government as such runs high on both sides of the Atlantic -- and seldom in
recent memory has there been a more compelling popular sentiment for a new
politics, even a new social dispensation that can give to people a sense of
direction that allows for security and ethical meaning. If the failure of
anarchism to address this situation can be attributed to any single source, the
insularity of lifestyle anarchism and its individualistic underpinnings must be
singled out for aborting the entry of a potential left-libertarian movement into
an ever-contracting public sphere. To its credit, anarchosyndicalism in its
heyday tried to engage in a living practice and create an organized movement --
so alien to lifestyle anarchism -- within the working class. Its major problems
lay not in its desire for structure and involvement, for program and social
mobilization, but in the waning of the working class as a revolutionary subject,
particularly after the Spanish Revolution. To say that anarchism lacked a
politics, however, conceived in its original Greek meaning as the self-management
of the community -- the historic 'Commune of communes' -- is to repudiate a
historic and transformative practice that seeks to radicalize the democracy
inherent in any republic and to create a municipalist confederal power to
countervail the state. The most creative feature of traditional anarchism is
its commitment to four basic tenets: a confederation of decentralized
municipalities; an unwavering opposition to statism; a belief in direct
democracy; and a vision of a libertarian communist society. The most important
issue that left-libertarianism -- libertarian socialism no less than anarchism --
faces today is: What will it do with these four powerful tenets? How will we give
them social form and content? In what ways and by what means will we render them
relevant to our time and bring them to the service of an organized popular
movement for empowerment and freedom? Anarchism must not be dissipated in
self-indulgent behavior like that of the primitivistic Adamites of the sixteenth
century, who 'wandered through the woods naked, singing and dancing,' as Kenneth
Rexroth contemptuously observed, spending 'their time in a continuous sexual
orgy' until they were hunted down by Jan Zizka and exterminated -- much to the
relief of a disgusted peasantry, whose lands they had plundered. [45] It must not
retreat into the primitivistic demimonde of the John Zerzans and George
Bradfords. I would be the last to contend that anarchists should not live their
anarchism as much as possible on a day-to-day basis -- personally as well as
socially, aesthetically as well as pragmatically. But they should not live an
anarchism that diminishes, indeed effaces the most important features that have
distinguished anarchism, as a movement, practice, and program, from statist
socialism. Anarchism today must resolutely retain its character as a social
movement -- a programmatic as well as activist social movement -- a movement that
melds its embattled vision of a libertarian communist society with its forthright
critique of capitalism, unobscured by names like 'industrial society.' In
short, social anarchism must resolutely affirm its differences with lifestyle
anarchism. If a social anarchist movement cannot translate its fourfold tenets --
municipal confederalism, opposition to statism, direct democracy, and ultimately
libertarian communism -- into a lived practice in a new public sphere; if these
tenets languish like its memories of past struggles in ceremonial pronouncements
and meetings; worse still, if they are subverted by the 'libertarian' Ecstasy
Industry and by quietistic Asian theisms, then its revolutionary socialistic core
will have to be restored under a new name. Certainly, it is already no longer
possible, in my view, to call oneself an anarchist without adding a qualifying
adjective to distinguish oneself from lifestyle anarchists. Minimally, social
anarchism is radically at odds with anarchism focused on lifestyle,
neo-Situationist paeans to ecstasy, and the sovereignty of the ever-shriveling
petty-bourgeois ego. The two diverge completely in their defining principles --
socialism or individualism. Between a committed revolutionary body of ideas and
practice, on the one hand, and a vagrant yearning for privatistic ecstasy and
self-realization on the other, there can be no commonality. Mere opposition to
the state may well unite fascistic lumpens with Stirnerite lumpens, a phenomenon
that is not without its historical precedents. -- June 1, 1995 Notes
1. The Political Philosophy of Bakunin, G. P. Maximoff editor (Glencoe, Ill.:
Free Press, 1953), p. 144.
2. Political Philosophy of Bakunin, p. 158.
3. Peter Kropotkin, 'Anarchism,' the Encyclopaedia Britannica article, in
Kropotkin's Revolutionary Pamphlets, ed. Roger N. Baldwin (New York: Dover
Publications, 1970), pp. 285-87.
4. Katinka Matson, 'Preface,' The
Psychology Today Omnibook of Personal Development (New York: William Morrow &
Co., 1977), n.p.
5. Michel Foucault, The History of Sexuality, vol. 1,
translated by Robert Hurley (New York: Vintage Books, 1990), pp. 95-96. Heavenly
will be the day when one can get straightforward formulations from Foucault,
interpretations of whose views are often contradictory.
6. Paul Goodman,
'Politics Within Limits,' in Crazy Hope and Finite Experience: Final Essays of
Paul Goodman, ed. Taylor Stoehr (San Francisco: Jossey-Bass, 1994), p. 56.
7. L. Susan Brown, The Politics of Individualism (Montreal: Black Rose Books,
1993). Brown's hazy commitment to anarchocommunism seems to derive more from a
visceral preference than from her analysis.
8. Hakim Bey, T.A.Z.: The
Temporary Autonomous Zone, Ontological Anarchism, Poetic Terrorism (Brooklyn, NY:
Autonomedia, 1985, 1991). Bey's individualism might easily resemble that of the
late Fredy Perlman and his anticivilizational acolytes and primitivists in
Detroit's Fifth Estate, except that T.A.Z. rather confusedly calls for 'a psychic
paleolithism based on High-Tech' (p. 44).
9. 'T.A.Z.,' The Whole Earth
Review (Spring 1994), p. 61.
10. Cited by Jose Lopez-Rey, Goya's Capriccios:
Beauty, Reason and Caricature, vol. 1 (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University
Press, 1953), pp. 80-81.
11. George Bradford, 'Stopping the Industrial
Hydra: Revolution Against the Megamachine,' The Fifth Estate, vol. 24, no. 3
(Winter 1990), p. 10.
12. Jacques Ellul, The Technological Society (New
York: Vintage Books, 1964), p. 430.
13. Bradford, 'Civilization in Bulk,
Fifth Estate (Spring 1991), p. 12.
14. Lewis Mumford, Technics and
Civilization (New York and Burlingame: Harcourt Brace & World, 1963), p. 301.
All page numbers herein refer to this edition.
15. Kropotkin, 'Anarchism,'
Revolutionary Pamphlets, p. 285.
16. The conference papers were published in
Richard B. Lee and Irven DeVore, eds., Man the Hunter (Chicago: Aldine Publishing
Co., 1968).
17. 'What Hunters Do for a Living, or, How to Make Out in Scarce
Resources,' in Lee and Devore, Man the Hunter, p. 43.
18. See particularly
Paul Radin's The World of Primitive Man (New York: Grove Press, 1953), pp.
139-150.
19. John Zerzan, Future Primitive and Other Essays (Brooklyn, NY:
Autonomedia, 1994), p. 16. The reader who has faith in Zerzan's research may try
looking for important sources like 'Cohen (1974)' and 'Clark (1979)' (cited on
pages 24 and 29, respectively) in his bibliography -- they and others are
entirely absent.
20. The literature on these aspects of prehistoric life is
very large. Anthony Legge and Peter A. Rowly's 'Gazelle Killing in Stone Age
Syria,' Scientific American, vol. 257 (Aug. 1987), pp. 88-95, shows that
migrating animals could have been slaughtered with devastating effectiveness by
the use of corrals. The classical study of the pragmatic aspects of animism is
Bronislaw Malinowski's Myth, Science and Religion (Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday,
1954). Manipulative anthropomorphization is evident in many accounts of
transmigrations from the human to nonhuman realm claimed by shamans, as in the
myths of the Makuna reported by Kaj 'rhem, 'Dance of the Water People,' Natural
History (Jan. 1992).
21. On the pygmies, see Colin M. Turnbull, The Forest
People: A Study of the Pygmies of the Congo (New York: Clarion/Simon and
Schuster, 1961), pp. 101-102. On the Eskimos, see Gontran de Montaigne Poncins's
Kabloona: A White Man in the Arctic Among the Eskimos (New York: Reynal &
Hitchcock, 1941), pp. 208-9, as well as in many other works on traditional Eskimo
culture.
22. That many grasslands throughout the world were produced by
fire, probably dating back to Homo erectus, is a hypothesis scattered throughout
the anthropological literature. An excellent study is Stephen J. Pyne's Fire in
America (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1982). See also William M.
Denevan, in Annals of the American Association of Geographers (Sept. 1992), cited
in William K. Stevens, 'An Eden in Ancient America? Not Really,' The New York
Times (March 30, 1993), p. C1.
23. On the hotly debated issue of 'overkill'
see Pleistocene Extinctions: The Search for a Cause, ed. P. S. Martin and H. E.
Wright, Jr. . The arguments around whether climatic factors and/or human
'overkilling' led to massive extinctions of some thirty-five genera of
Pleistocene mammals are too complex to be dealt with here. See Paul S. Martin,
'Prehistoric Overkill,' in Pleistocene Extinctions: The Search for a Cause, ed.
P. S. Martin and H. E. Wright, Jr. (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1967). I
have explored some of the arguments in my introduction to the 1991 revised
edition of The Ecology of Freedom (Montreal: Black Rose Books). The evidence is
still under debate. Mastodons, who were once regarded as environmentally
restricted animals, are now known to have been ecologically more flexible and
might have been killed off by Paleoindian hunters, possibly with far less
compunction than romantic environmentalists would like to believe. I do not
contend that hunting alone pushed these large mammals to extermination -- a
considerable amount of killing would have been enough.
A summary of arroyo
drives of bison can be found in Brian Fagan, 'Bison Hunters of the Northern
Plains,' Archaeology (May-June 1994), p. 38.
24. Karl W. Butzer, 'No Eden in
the New World,' Nature, vol. 82 (March 4, 1993), pp. 15-17.
25. T. Patrick
Cuthbert, 'The Collapse of Classic Maya Civilization,' in The Collapse of Ancient
States and Civilizations, ed. Norman Yoffee and George L. Cowgill (Tucson, Ariz.:
University of Arizona Press, 1988); and Joseph A. Tainter, The Collapse of
Complex Societies (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), esp. chapter
5.
26. Clifford Geertz, 'Life on the Edge,' The New York Review of Books,
April 7, 1994, p. 3.
27. As William Powers observes, the book 'Black Elk
Speaks was published in 1932. There is no trace of Black Elk's Christian life in
it.' For a thorough debunking of the current fascination with the Black Elk
story, see William Powers, 'When Black Elk Speaks, Everybody Listens,' Social
Text, vol. 8, no. 2 (1991), pp. 43-56.
28. Edwin N. Wilmsen, Land Filled
With Flies (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1989), p. 127.
29.
Wilmsen, Land Filled with Flies, p. 3.
30. Allyn Maclean Stearman, Yuqu':
Forest Nomads in a Changing World (Fort Worth and Chicago: Holt, Rinehart and
Winston, 1989), p. 23.
31. Stearman, Yuqu', pp. 80-81.
32. Wilmsen,
Land Filled with Flies, pp. 235-39 and 303-15.
33. See, for example, Robert
J. Blumenschine and John A. Cavallo, 'Scavenging and Human Evolution,' Scientific
American (October 1992), pp. 90-96.
34. Paul A. Janssens, Paleopathology:
Diseases and Injuries of Prehistoric Man (London: John Baker, 1970).
35.
Wood, Human Sickness, p. 20.
36. E. B. Maple, 'The Fifth Estate Enters the
20th Century. We Get a Computer and Hate It!' The Fifth Estate, vol. 28, no. 2
(Summer 1993), pp. 6-7.
37. Quoted in The New York Times, May 7, 1995. Less
sanctimonious people than Zerzan have tried to escape the hold of television and
take their pleasures with decent music, radio plays, books, and the like. They
just don't buy them!
38. Max Stirner, The Ego and His Own, ed. James J.
Martin, trans. Steven T. Byington (New York: Libertarian Book Club, 1963), part
2, chap. 4, sec. C, 'My Self-Engagement,' p. 352, emphasis added.
39.
Friedrich Nietzsche, 'On Truth and Lie in an Extra-Moral Sense' (1873; fragment),
in The Portable Nietzsche, edited and translated by Walter Kaufmann (New York:
Viking Portable Library, 1959), pp. 46-47.
40. Friedrich Nietzsche, fragment
481 (1883-1888), The Will to Power, trans. Walter Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale
(New York: Random House, 1967), p. 267.
41. James J. Martin, editor's
introduction to Stirner, Ego and His Own, p. xviii.
42. Max Horkheimer, The
Eclipse of Reason (New York: Oxford University Press, 1947), p. 135.
43.
Kropotkin, 'Anarchism,' Revolutionary Pamphlets, pp. 287, 293.
44.
Kropotkin, 'Anarchism,' Revolutionary Pamphlets, pp. 292-93.
45. Kenneth
Rexroth, Communalism (New York: Seabury Press, 1974), p. 89. I would like to
thank my colleague and companion, Janet Biehl, for her invaluable assistance in
researching material for and editing this essay.
From AK Press: Social Anarchism or Lifestyle Anarchism: An Unbridgeable Chasm
by Murray Bookchin, $7.95/pound 5.95, ISBN #1-873176-83-X. Available from AK
Press, PO Box 40682, San Francisco, CA 94140-0682 and AK Press, 22 Lutton Place,
Edinburgh, Scotland EH8 9PE.